Bipin Balaram
“What
makes them representatives of the petty bourgeoisie is the fact that in their
minds they do not get beyond the limits that the latter do not get beyond in
life, that they are consequently driven, theoretically, to the same problems
and solutions to which material interest and social position drive the latter
in practice.” – Karl Marx (18th Brumaire of Louie Bonaparte)
The
Patnaiks are out to disprove Lenin and to improve Marx. The theory of
imperialism put forward by Prabhat Patnaik and Utsa Patnaik[1]
attempts to do this by proving that Lenin’s theory of imperialism is no longer
valid. They also assert that Marx’s (and everyone else’s until now!) analysis
of capitalism is incomplete because it failed to include the analysis of
imperialism. Of course, these serious flaws shall be put right by the theory of
imperialism proposed by the Patnaiks. In the beginning of the book itself, the
Patnaiks make the purpose of their book clear:
“The
purpose of the present book is to argue … that there is an abiding relevance to
the concept of “imperialism”. It seeks to establish that there is a continuity
between the colonial period and now … This continuity arises from a certain structural
relationship that characterises capitalism but that, surprisingly, has received
very little attention until now. Put differently, in addition to the capital
– wage labour relationship, capitalism is characterised by an additional
structural relationship, and “imperialism” refers to that structural
relationship … its essence lies in the fact that capitalism, … must, in its
“spontaneous” operation, act in ways that tend to immiserate the traditional
petty producers of the third world, who constitute the overwhelming bulk of the
working population of these countries.”[2]
Poor
Marx could only fathom the first of the two structural relationships that
characterise capitalism, about the second one he had no inkling! But Lenin’s
sin, contends the Patnaiks, is much greater as, in his over enthusiasm to
explain the conjuncture of the First World War, he put forward a theory of
imperialism which has lost its validity now:
“When
Lenin was writing about imperialism, his perception was of a set of rival
imperialist powers, each characterised by a financial oligarchy that presided
over a coalition of banks and industrial capital, was closely integrated with
that country’s state personnel, and was engaged in partitioning and
re-partitioning the world in the quest for ‘economic territory’ … These
features have been largely superseded by the emergence, through further
centralisation of capital, of international finance capital that is globalised,
is not tied to any particular nation-state, …, is more financial in nature, and
is engaged in massive speculation for capital gains, rather than being with the
promotion of industry … International finance capital therefore specifically
wants a muting of inter-imperialist rivalry … which has been a feature of the
scenario sketched by Lenin.”[3]
We
shall enter into the merits of Patnaiks’ above assertions about Lenin’s theory
of imperialism later in this article, but it is very clear what the Patnaiks
are asserting - the emergence of international finance capital and the ‘muting’
of inter imperialist rivalries has proved Lenin wrong and has vindicated the
Kautskian thesis of ‘ultra-imperialism’. That the Patnaiks never considers it
important to mention the uncanny similarity between Kautsky’s ultra-imperialism
and their analysis and makes no effort even to delineate their position
vis-à-vis that of Kautsky’s tell us a lot!
Even
when the real aim of the book is to disprove Lenin and to improve Marx, there
is a conscious effort to camouflage this aim with false modesty. This starts
from the name of the book itself. It has been named ‘A Theory of Imperialism’,
the suggestion being that it is advanced only as one among many worthy theories
of imperialism (Lenin’s included?) and not as substitute for others. The
authors themselves make this clear in their preface to the book:
“It
is not our intention to present this theory as a substitute for, or as an
alternative to, the existing theories of imperialism. We are simply attempting
to draw attention to certain phenomena that have always characterised
capitalism and continue to do so even now. These phenomena underlie capitalism
but have not received the attention they deserve. They are ensconced within a
universe that has been much studied by writers on imperialism; our
concentration on them alone while not discussing these other studies, should
not be construed as detracting from the worth of these theories.”[4]
The
Patnaiks’ argument that they are only trying to highlight certain aspects of
capitalism which have not received enough attention and that this should not be
seen as effort to present an alternative to other existing theories of
imperialism is patently false. For example, as we shall see in detail later,
the Patnaiks offer a definition of imperialism which is completely at
odds with Lenin’s definition of imperialism as the monopoly stage of
capitalism. They define imperialism as a particular way in which
capitalism deals with a fundamental geographical asymmetry between the
temperate and tropical regions of the world. If this definition is the correct
one, then it means that Lenin’s is absurd. Patnaiks’ definition implies
that imperialism has nothing what so ever
to do with the monopoly stage of capitalism; it had existed in all stages of
capitalism. If, on the other hand, Lenin’s definition is correct, then the
Patnaiks’ whole theory is false. Such conflicting definitions cannot lead to
theories which can lie beside one another and complete each other, they lead to conflicting theories out
of which only one can be correct. Hence, one would do well not to be
fooled by this false modesty, it is a sham. The Patnaiks want to radically
revise all the basic positions of Marxism – Leninism regarding imperialism but
still want to retain the tag of Marxists; hence the effort to “ensconce”[5]
their theory within Marxist-Leninist ideas on imperialism and to declare it as
not at odds with them. The main aim of this article is to drive out the
Patnaiks’ theory from where it wants to “ensconce” itself, to unmask its
untenable character from a Marxist perspective, to unearth the authors’ main
motivation in presenting such a flimsy theory and to consign it to where it
belongs – the dust heap of history.
1. The Context of Patnaiks’ Theory –
Blatant Reformism of Indian Social Democratic Left
In
his hard hitting commentary on the Patnaiks’ theory of imperialism, included in
the book itself, David Harvey wonders[6]
why the Patnaiks have put forward a theory based on such obviously wrong
premises and which gets the “concepts of space, place, environment, and geography
all wrong”[7]. The
Patnaiks’ enthusiasm to advance laborious and obviously false (and sometimes
even bordering on ridiculous) premises and results can only be understood by
taking a look at the class basis of Indian left’s (academic and political)
current political positions[8]. It
will be seen later that the main motivating factor of the book is to conjure up
a theoretical framework which can implicitly defend the reformist and social
democratic positions that the Indian left professes and which are completely
untenable from a Marxist-Leninist perspective. The flimsy theoretical tweaks
that the Patnaiks’ make have only one overriding purpose: to render the reformist
ideology and regressive politics of Indian left progressive. So, we have to
begin our analysis by having a look at Indian left’s current positions and we
shall do so by using some typical and illuminating examples.
It
is first useful to see how the left approach imperialism in practice; that is,
what is their anti-imperialist stance on the ground? In actual political practice, on the ground, it can be
observed that the main form that the left led anti-imperialist struggles take
is against the destruction of the petty bourgeois by 'imperialist corporates'.
The left no longer recognises any difference between a wage labourer, a shop
keeper, an auto-rickshaw driver, a small farmer or a state clerk; all are
subsumed under the name of worker, all are characterized as poor, and
anti-imperialism takes the form of 'protecting' their interests (yes, interests
of all of them, simultaneously!) against the vile designs of the international
giants. Of course on the ground, this 'classless', 'pro-poor', populist
approach gives the left rich dividends in the form of votes till it runs
against its own contradictions and bursts asunder. But the fact that this
benevolent pro poor strategy is diametrically opposed to the classical Marxist approach
to the destruction of petty production gives a head ache or two to the left
academicians. Not only in the question of imperialism, but on all fronts, the
social democratic left in India has long since forsaken class analysis of
social problems and have succumbed to the vulgar form of petty bourgeois
populism. In the case of imperialism, it means that the left now squarely see it
as an affair between countries alone and not one between classes; Patnaiks’
theory attempts to give this vulgar populist approach a theoretical foundation. A classic example of this populist
approach is provided by a recent facebook post by M. A. Baby, a PB member of
the CPIM. On the occasion of Argentina’s victory over the US in Copa America football championships, Baby
wrote:
“I congratulate the Argentinian national team on
entering the finals of the Copa America football tournament after defeating the
US. For communists throughout the world like me, it is thrilling to see the US
being defeated, in whichever field. That thrill increases this time as they
were defeated by Che Guevara’s countrymen.”[9]
This shows us the extent to which the reformist left
has stooped; for them anti-imperialism essentially means hating the US, wailing
about how their corporates are destroying our small shopkeepers and wishing
earnestly that the US is defeated in football matches!
Return to ‘Welfare State’
Even
Irfan Habib, otherwise a very perceptive historian and someone who has used the
Marxist method very creatively on questions of Indian history, cannot resist
arriving at reformist conclusions when analysing concrete political questions.
In his recent analysis of the growth of Hindutva fascism in India, he arrives
at the conclusion that:
“A
serious task awaits parties that are committed to a different future for the
country, envisaging a truly secular democratic India, where reason and science
might serve to sustain a welfare state. Perhaps the conflict over whether such
a state would be socialist or a free market one can be postponed until the
present crisis is over.”[10]
In
many ways, this is a typical reaction of the Indian social democratic left.
Three
points should immediately be highlighted:
1 A
welfare state, which aims at looking after the welfare of all the people,
including the bourgeois and the proletariat, can never be socialist. A
proletarian state is the dictatorship of one class over another which do not
intend to look after the welfare of the bourgeoisie. So a welfare state is a
bourgeois state conceived to pacify the proletariat before switching over to
full blooded capitalist loot.
2. The
typical reaction of the Indian left on the face of crisis, political or
economic, is to go back. The nostalgia for welfare state and Nehruvian
socialism is so strong that it is practically the only solution the
whole left has to offer – back to ‘secular democratic India’. Going back to
‘crisis less’, state administered, safe capitalism with its security net for
the petty producers is a petty bourgeois illusion.
3. Welfare
state is never a solution to fascism; fascism has come precisely because
of the implosion of the welfare state. Capitalism in perpetual crisis breeds
fascism and the solution is not an illusionary retreat to crisis less, state
managed capitalism, but transcendence of capitalism itself.
In
their critique of the neoliberal economic reforms in India[11],
JNU economists and left academicians C. P. Chandrasekhar and Jayati Ghosh try
to demonstrate the failure of neoliberalism in India. And their solution is,
again, an ‘activist state’!
“There
are two prerequisites for such a state. It should be willing to launch an
alternate strategy that permits a degree of autonomy from the agenda imposed by
international finance. And it should be able to undertake the progressive
structural reforms which would be necessary to create the social base and
sanction for such an effort. India awaits the emergence of such a state.”
Degree
of autonomy from international finance has since then become a general solution
for the left and goes by the name of ‘de-linking’ now. The second point calls
for the creation of a welfare state. So the solution is nothing but a welfare
state free from the clutches of international finance; a modern incarnation of
Nehruvian state. The contradictions of the welfare state have given rise to
neoliberalism but the only solution that is offered is to go back to the petty
bourgeois bliss of the welfare state; going forward from neoliberalism to
socialism does not even enter the minds of Indian left!
When
the current BJP government dismantled one of the last relics of the welfare
state era by disbanding
the planning commission, the feelings of the Indian left were hurt, they were
wounded. Nostalgia for the comfortable days of crisis free capitalism was at
its peak and C. P. Chandrasekhar expressed it emotionally[12]:
“… India’s planners served as the conscience-keepers in a market driven
environment that privileges profit and power.” Needless to say that this is a
completely wrong reading of the welfare state interlude of Indian
capitalism[13].
De-linking
and Nationalism
Following
the left front’s crushing defeat in the parliamentary elections and in the
Bengal state legislature elections following that, Prabhat Patnaik himself
detailed the ‘things the left needs to do right’[14].
He came up with the revelation that the slide of communism world-wide after
WWII was caused by its ambivalent attitude towards globalisation and democracy.
So he urged the left to shed this ambivalence and to espouse ‘de-linking’ from
globalisation and to embrace democracy.
“…
uniting with others in struggles and on platforms, and even in government,
against the Hindutva and semi-fascist forces and on the basis of concrete
alternative agenda to neoliberalism, will serve the people better.”[15]
For
Patnaik, “shedding” ambivalence towards globalisation and democracy means
‘de-linking’ from globalisation and embracing liberal democracy. This cannot be
reconciled with the Leninist ideas on globalisation, imperialism and democracy.
Patnaik knows that fully, but has an ingenious plan. He declares that Lenin,
with whatever he has to say, is irrelevant to us right now:
“But
already at the end of the second world war, the world had started moving away
from what one can call the ‘Leninist conjuncture’ … the Leninist conjuncture
has been superseded … because the premise upon which it was founded no longer
held, the premise of an imminent world revolution.”
I
have argued elsewhere why this fading away of Lenin is just wishful thinking
from a professor who is uncomfortable with the revolutionary kernel of Lenin’s
writings. I have also argued that actuality of revolution and not its imminence
is the premise of Leninism and that Leninism is the living, throbbing,
motoring force of history right now which the toiling class has to imbibe.
I shall not repeat them here[16].
But
Patnaik do realise that his call to de-link from globalisation may be construed
as a return to nationalism. He says that this fear is at the root of European
left’s ambivalence towards globalisation.
“…
no matter how objectionable it finds the hegemony of finance capital which
characterises globalisation, it cannot contemplate shaking off this hegemony
through a delinking from globalisation , because it sees any such delinking as
revival of ‘nationalism’ which it abhors.”
During
the Kanhaiyya Kumar episode, when the debate on ‘nationalism’ raged, Patnaik had the opportunity to
develop this point further and to assure us that in the Indian context we need
not have any qualms about nationalism, because the Indian version of
nationalism is ‘democratic and egalitarian’.
“European
nationalism in short was an aggrandising nationalism … the concept of
“nationalism” that developed in countries like India during their anti-colonial
struggle was of an altogether different kind … it
had to be inclusive … had to have a fraternal rather than an aggrandising
relation with other Third World countries. And finally, it had to put the welfare
of the “people”, as distinct from the greatness of the “nation” per se, as its
central focus … This was a nationalism which was sui generis, an altogether new
phenomenon the like of which the world had not seen earlier. It was essentially
a democratic and egalitarian nationalism as opposed to the aggrandising
European nationalism.”[17]
So
the Indian left need not worry like their European counterparts, their
nationalism is progressive. But he realises that “…the democratic
nationalism of the anti-colonial struggle is not easy to realise”, and that
“…The shift to an aggrandising nationalism is clearly linked to the
emergence of neo-liberal capitalism in the country.” So, in order to
realise the progressive and egalitarian version of Indian nationalism, we obviously
need to shun neoliberalism and to delink from globalisation to build a welfare
state. Hence, we need not have any misgivings about going back to ‘good’
nationalism!
It
is amusing to see how Patnaik, who calls himself a Marxist, divorces the
analysis of nationalism completely from material conditions and history.
Marxism studies every social phenomenon, including nationalism, by looking at
the material conditions that breeds them and situating them in the concrete
historical context. Thus, to compare European nationalism that arose during the
consolidation of capitalism with its third world variety which arose much later
in the context of anti-colonial struggles is in itself unhistorical. But to
maintain that European nationalism always had and will have an aggrandising
character and that the Indian variety always was and will be progressive
is stooping to newer depths. Patnaik implies that the character of nationalism
remains fixed and do not evolve in history or change with changing material
conditions. Thus, Indian nationalism was born progressive and shall
remain so, forever.
Lenin
had anticipated this petty bourgeois fixation of the social democrats towards
nationalism and had clearly delineated the Marxist approach towards national
movements and nationalism.
“The principle of nationality is historically
inevitable in bourgeois society and, taking this society into due account, the Marxist
fully recognises the historical legitimacy of national movements. But to
prevent this recognition from becoming an apologia of nationalism, it must be
strictly limited to what is progressive in such movements, in order that this
recognition may not lead to bourgeois ideology obscuring proletarian
consciousness.
The
awakening of the masses from feudal lethargy, and their struggle against all
national oppression, for the sovereignty of the people, of the nation, are
progressive. Hence, it is the Marxist’s bounden duty to stand for the most
resolute and consistent democratism on all aspects of the national question.
This task is largely a negative one. But this is the limit the proletariat can
go to in supporting nationalism, for beyond that begins the “positive”
activity of the bourgeoisie striving to fortify nationalism.
To throw off the feudal yoke, all national oppression,
and all privileges enjoyed by any particular nation or language, is the
imperative duty of the proletariat as a democratic force, and is certainly in
the interests of the proletarian class struggle, which is obscured and retarded
by bickering on the national question. But to go beyond these strictly
limited and definite historical limits in helping bourgeois nationalism means
betraying the proletariat and siding with the bourgeoisie. There is a
border-line here, which is often very slight …”[18]
It
is exactly this slight border-line that is invisible to theorists like Patnaik
because of their petty bourgeois orientation. He is theorising about
‘progressive’ and ‘aggrandising’ nationalisms with no reference to the stage of
capitalism. What we have before our eyes is the form that the progressive,
democratic and egalitarian nationalism has taken in the time of capitalist
decay. If one refuses to see this dynamic nature of nationalism – from
progressive to chauvinistic – and its necessary change with the change in the
nature of capitalism, then he is never a Marxist – Leninist.
We know that the same mistake was committed by
the left in the JNU affair. The left built their case on the distinction
between good and bad nationalism, i.e. between democratic, people-oriented
nationalism and the chauvinist variety. The class essence of this distinction
is simple. The left positioned themselves on the side of bourgeois-democratic
nationalism and the far right was (correctly) pictured as chauvinist nationalists;
the former thought of as being progressive and the latter reactionary. This
meant that the left had only one practical
prescription: shun chauvinism and embrace ‘good’ nationalism, a nationalism
whose spirit was thought to be
imbibed from the freedom struggle. Needless to say that such a line had nothing
to do with historical materialism which locates nationalism as a strictly
bourgeois ideology. This ideology can be a progressive force only
till bourgeoisie remains a progressive class or till capitalism is still in its
progressive phase. As capitalism enters its decaying, moribund phase,
nationalism, being a bourgeois ideology,
turns into its chauvinistic twin. Proletarian movements support national
struggles only in the progressive phase of capitalism, that too in a qualified
sense. Going back to ‘good’ nationalism is an illusion as it needs progressive
capitalism to be brought back. This political line betrays
the social democratic orientation of Indian parliamentary left which seeks to
ameliorate capitalism, rather than to transcend it. But, in their over
enthusiasm to reform capitalism, they forget that zombies cannot be brought back to life! Left failed to explain the bourgeois-democratic class
nature of nationalist ideology, its metamorphosis into chauvinism as a
necessary consequence of the decay of capitalism and the need to espouse
proletarian internationalism in its stead. The practical fallout of left’s line
became evident very soon. The left’s embrace of bourgeois-democratic
nationalism robbed them of the possibility of putting forward the platform of genuine
solidarity between the toiling masses across the borders. Arun Jaitley was
correct when he said that the sangh parivar won the battle of JNU as the left
was forced to convert themselves to ‘nationalists’ overnight!
Democracy
and Parliament
Now
that delinking has been thoroughly theorised and the misgivings on nationalism
dealt with, what remains is to explain why we should embrace ‘democracy’.
Orthodox Marxist – Leninist positions on ‘freedom’ and ‘democracy’, as
political facades of capitalism, are too well known to be evaded. Hence,
Patnaik and the left feels the need to theorise the ‘return to democracy’. This
he does when analysing widespread corruption and the resultant erosion of popular
faith in Parliament.
“… “corruption” discourse also has some Left
adherents. They argue that the discrediting of the institution of Parliament by
the corruption discourse need not be lamented. Parliament after all is a
bourgeois democratic institution and if the “people” are disillusioned with it,
and thus the Left should be with the “people” rather than defending this
institution. But idealising the “people” in this manner is wrong for two
obvious reasons: first, the “people” who are vocal in their anger against
Parliament constitute a subset, which is by no means representative of the
people at large… Second, even the people at large as they are, should not be
apotheosised by the Left which is concerned with changing people’s
consciousness rather than bowing before it.”[19]
He
continues:
“Further,
since Parliament, such as it is, is based on a formal principle of equality
(“one person one vote”), which is alien to the consciousness inculcated by
millennia of institutionalised inequality embedded in the caste system, its
being discredited as an institution can be used for discrediting this principle
itself, for reinforcing a culture of inequality which feeds into fascism. To
believe the contrary, namely, that a discrediting of this bourgeois democratic
institution would strengthen the revolutionary rather than the fascist forces,
is an illusion. Neo-liberalism, it was mentioned earlier, tends to produce a
“closure” of politics, a snuffing out of any transformative agenda that goes
beyond neo-liberalism itself. The stasis that such a closure generates is not
overcome by, and indeed is quite compatible with, the prolonged existence of an
armed insurgency, based on a particular segment of the oppressed corralled into
a particular region, and itself in a state of stagnation or recession. Fascism
attempts to use the popular anger against this stasis: it gives the impression
of breaking out of it, while actually strongly reinforcing neo-liberalism
through a merger of corporate and state power. A discrediting of Parliament as
an institution, in this context, removes a potential bulwark against such a
shift.”
I
have quoted this argument in full because it is a great example of the abuse of
language by the academicians to give us the semblance that a seemingly
untenable position has much more to it than what meets the eye and that it is
justified based on a deeper logic. This deeper logic is so deep that it is
buried somewhere inside this verbal diarrhoea so that we ordinary mortals are
incapable of deciphering it!
As
stated by Patnaik himself, parliament is based on ‘formal’ equality, not real
equality. ‘One person, one vote’ has nothing to do with real equality. Even
this ‘formal’ equality was progressive during nationalist struggle when India
had to break down the colonial yoke and feudal backwardness. It is no longer
now when capitalism is in crisis. The contention that it is progressive for
ever arises out of a complete absence of historical dialectics in his
analysis. Discrediting the institution is discrediting the principle,
but it is time to discredit a principle which no longer retains its progressive
potential and have become regressive. And discrediting the institution and the
principle should be accompanied by a proper dialectical and revolutionary call
to take it forward, not backward, as Patnaik implicitly assumes. His petty
bourgeois class instincts can fathom only two movements, either status quo or
backward. But there is one more movement, professor, and that is forward!
It
is said that neoliberalism produces closure of politics, doesn’t capitalism
produce that per se? Yes. It is the historical duty of the proletarian vanguard
to help the toilers to break out of this closure and to realise the foreword
march of history. Patnaik further says that fascism will try to make use of
this stasis to effect a merger of corporate and state power to reinforce
neoliberalism. So what should we do? We should not discredit parliament and
should prolong and cultivate the illusion that change is possible through it. Pathetic!
It is amusing to see Patnaik remarking that “…even the people at large as
they are, should not be apotheosised by the Left which is concerned with
changing people’s consciousness rather than bowing before it.” So, how exactly does he want the left to
change peoples’ consciousness regarding the parliament and bourgeois democracy?
Obviously not by explaining their class roots to them. Instead, he wants the left
to drag back the spontaneous anger against liberal democracy and to explain to
the people why it is important to sustain it; he evidently abhors the idea of
the left channelling this anger to explain to the toilers the need to take
non-performing liberal democracy forward to real proletarian democracy. This
is the same petty bourgeois logic that the Mensheviks advanced during the 1905
revolution when they said that criticising the bourgeois institutions will help
the reactionaries to roll back democracy. An effort by the fascists to ‘go
back’ by smashing the parliament cannot be countered by trying to retain it, it is the decay of parliament
that is giving legitimacy to the fascist call to destroy it. It can only be met in
a revolutionary way by pulling it in the opposite direction, i.e., by standing
for the transcendence of decaying bourgeois democracy and with it, capitalism
.
Lenin
demolished the same reverence for parliament which was espoused by Kautsky:
“Take
the bourgeois parliament. Can it be that the learned Kautsky has never heard
that the more highly democracy is developed, the more the bourgeois parliaments
are subjected by the stock exchange and the bankers? This does not mean that we
must not make use of bourgeois parliament (the Bolsheviks made better use of it
than probably any other party in the world, for in 1912–14 we won the entire
workers’ curia in the Fourth Duma). But it does mean that only a liberal can
forget the historical limitations and conventional nature of the bourgeois
parliamentary system as Kautsky does. Even in the most democratic bourgeois
state the oppressed people at every step encounter the crying contradiction
between the formal equality proclaimed by the “democracy” of the capitalists
and the thousands of real limitations and subterfuges which turn the
proletarians into wage-slaves. It is precisely this contradiction that is
opening the eyes of the people to the rottenness, mendacity and hypocrisy of
capitalism. It is this contradiction that the agitators and propagandists of
socialism are constantly exposing to the people, in order to prepare them for
revolution! And now that the era of revolution has begun, Kautsky turns his
back upon it and begins to extol the charms of moribund bourgeois democracy…
To fail to see this one must either deliberately serve the bourgeoisie, or be
politically as dead as a doornail, unable to see real life from behind the
dusty pages of bourgeois books, be thoroughly imbued with bourgeois-democratic
prejudices, and thereby objectively convert oneself into a lackey of the
bourgeoisie.”[20]
Lenin
is as straight as an arrow regarding this, revolutionary movements should make
use of the parliament; they should make use of the parliament to expose its
limitations and to call for its transcendence. No wonder Patnaik maintains
that Lenin is irrelevant, because if he is relevant, Patnaik is ‘as dead as a
doornail’.
So,
we have seen, by way of examples, the regressive nature of the cure prescribed
by social democratic left and its intellectual representatives for the twin
malice that India is facing now: the alarming growth of fascist forces and the
state of decay of capitalism. A partial list of these proposals would include
the following steps:
a. Return
to an activist welfare state
b. Autonomy
from international finance capital and de-linking from globalisation
c. Shunning
aggrandising nationalism, embracing its democratic, egalitarian variety
d. Re-envisaging
a truly secular democratic India
e. Embracing
democracy, strengthening parliament
f. Uniting
with other ‘progressive’ parties.
We
have already seen how these steps are untenable from a Marxist perspective and how
they betray a complete lack of understanding of materialist and revolutionary
dialectics of history. The Patnaiks, even though their class instincts never
allow them to espouse Marxism’s revolutionary kernel, are too well read in
Marxism not to be aware of this fact. So it is not a surprise that they felt
the need to conjure up a new theory of imperialism which will render all
these steps apparently progressive!
In the following, we shall come across myriad exotic ways taken by the Patnaiks
to fulfil this arduous task: that of rendering social democracy anti-imperialist
and hence progressive.
2.
The Patnaiks’ Theory of Imperialism
We
shall now take a look at the main aspects of the Patnaiks’ theory of
imperialism. I shall present these aspects using extensive direct quotes from
the book. This is necessitated by the fact that many of the premises and
conclusions of the book are so ludicrous that if I attempt to paraphrase them
in my own words, many readers may find it hard to believe that the authors actually
advanced such theses.
Tropical
Commodities and Geographical Asymmetry
Let
us hear from the Patnaiks themselves what the purpose of their book is:
“Its
purpose has been altogether different and rather sui generis. It has asked the
question: Is it necessary for metropolitan capital always to enter into a
structural relationship with the people of the periphery, which entails a
subjugation of the latter? … The purpose of this book has been to argue that
there is indeed a compelling economic reason for metropolitan capital to
subjugate, and to maintain continuous ascendancy over, the people of the
periphery.”[21]
This
subjugation is neither on
account of the rising predominance of export of capital vis-à-vis export of
commodities in the age of imperialism and the need to defend the interests of
the capital exporting core, as pointed out by Lenin, nor on account of the need
for markets for core capitalism as asserted by Luxemburg. This need for
expansion has also nothing to do with the fall in the rate of profit in
advanced capitalist countries. In fact, it has nothing to do with capitalism at
all! It is indeed sui generis.
“Metropolitan
capitalism requires a large range of commodities that are necessary for it
(including not only for the subsistence of the workers it employs but for
consumption by all classes) but that it cannot produce in the geographical
space within which it exists; nor can it develop substitutes for all of these
commodities. It must obtain them from outside of its space, i.e., from the periphery
constituting the global South, where they are produced by a host of
pre-capitalist petty producers and typically in conditions that entail an
“increasing supply price.”[22]
Thus,
Patnaiks’ theory suggests that the original sin of imperialism is to be
sought not in capitalism, but in spatial or geographical asymmetry with respect
to the availability of certain commodities. Imperialism is the way in which
capitalism deals with this asymmetry. This point gives the authors a lot of theoretical
problems throughout the
book and they are at pains to
prove that their theory does not rest on geography but on capitalism.
Another point to be noted here is their assertion that these commodities are “produced
by a host of pre-capitalist petty producers” in the periphery. This is a
central tenet of their theory, the correctness of which we shall examine later.
But what exactly are these commodities?
“These
goods include today not only the traditional imported crops (such as cane
sugar, spices, tea, coffee, cereals, and fibres) but also all those perishable
vegetables, fruits, and flowers that cold temperate lands can grow only in
their summer but not in their winter when the land is frozen, hence, the
necessity of imports to avoid seasonal lack of supply. So fresh carrots,
tomatoes, fruit, and flowers in December–January are, analytically speaking, to
be conceptualized as “tropical goods” for northern populations.”[23]
So,
this geographical asymmetry means that:
“…despite
all technological advances, import substitution is not possible at all as
regards a large range of tropical products in the temperate-region advanced
economies—where the definition of “tropical products” includes strawberries and
roses in December. The products of the tropical landmass, along with energy, are
an essential, taken-for-granted part of the daily requirements of advanced
countries, both as current inputs into production and for the consumption
basket of their populations.”[24]
Geographical
characteristics mean that advanced capitalist countries of temperate zone have
to forever rely on tropical landmass for these commodities. These primary
commodities, the authors further assert, have two main characteristics.
“The
first is that they are produced in distant outlying regions and typically by
petty producers who, though linked to capitalism and therefore no longer
retaining their original character, are nonetheless outside of the capital-wage
labour relationship.”[25]
So
the Patnaiks maintain, unequivocally, that these commodities needed for the
core are produced by petty producers who are ‘outside of the capital-wage
labour relationship’. What is more important is the fact that they make no
attempt what so ever in the book to see whether this situation is changing,
i.e., they do not attempt to trace the possible growth of capitalism in the
production of these commodities. They maintain throughout that petty production
is the only one that produces these commodities and do not attempt to see
whether the material basis of this petty production is breaking up. It is
amusing to see, further on in the book, the arguments they advance to prove
that capitalism cannot penetrate these sectors of production. This
should not be surprising as it is a common characteristic of ‘academicians’
that they tend to abstract in their brains and expect reality to
correspond to their abstraction. Hence the complete absence in the book of any real
data pertaining to the state of affairs in these sectors. Please note that
this is the beginning of the love story between the Patnaiks and petty
production that shall ‘live happily forever’ even after the book is over.
Let
us dwell a little bit on this first characteristic before proceeding to the
second one. At this point, one yearns for examples and the Patnaiks oblige. “Mineral
resources, in the absence of the discovery of new and more easily exploitable
sources, are a clear example of such a commodity.”[26] Ah, nice! Here is our
example. So, as mineral resources are examples of such commodities, it is
obvious that it has the first characteristic that the Patnaiks said such
commodities possess. No, it’s not that simple folks, seems that you are
not very familiar with the higher logic prevalent in academia. “They may not
be produced by petty producers, but they are produced in distant outlying regions,
and without supplies from these regions, the growing demand for them cannot be
met.”[27]
So, they are not produced by petty producers which means that they do not have
one characteristic out of two which the authors said they had, but that doesn’t
count; can’t you see that they are “produced in distant outlying regions”. And
all this happens in two adjacent pages!
So
what do we do? “While the argument of this book will also hold with suitable
modification for the case of mineral resources, we shall be concerned in what
follows primarily with products of the tropical landmass.”[28] It was that simple,
we shall concentrate on examples that suit us and just claim that, ‘with
suitable modification’, the arguments shall hold for other examples too. How
that can be done is not clear at all because if these commodities are not
produced by petty producers, then they follow a completely different course;
but that’s not a hindrance for the Patnaiks.
Let
it be. What is the second characteristic?
Increasing
Supply Price, Threat to the Value of Money and Income Deflation
“The
second characteristic is that these commodities are subject to the phenomenon
of increasing supply price, which means that if an increase in the demand for
them were to be satisfied by greater production, then even at the existing
level of money wage rate per efficiency unit of labour at the point of
production, or money income of the producers per unit of their labour (measured
in efficiency units), their unit prime cost of production would increase.”[29]
The
Patnaiks make their point a bit more clear later:
“Since
the tropical landmass is more or less fully used up, and since its products are
required in the metropolitan core located in the temperate world, capital
accumulation that enlarges the demand for such products must lead to a rise in
the price of such products. Such a rise in the price of these products will not
elicit larger outputs of these products from the tropical lands (on this more
later). But additionally, such a rise has serious implications for the
stability of the metropolitan economy.”[30]
So,
when the demand for the tropical products increase in temperate metropolitan
core because of capital accumulation, their price goes up. The Patnaiks’ argue
that such a rise in prices is going to effect the stability of metropolitan
economy itself. Before we see how, we need to realise that the authors have
slipped in a rather innocuous looking assumption here; they base their
arguments on the wish (as we shall see, it is no more than that) that the
tropical landmass is more or less fully used up. If it is not used up
and if there is a possibility of bringing more landmass under the plough, then
the Patnaiks’ argument that an increase in demand will lead to a rise in prices, falls flat. So, the whole
of Patnaiks’ theory is based on this assumption. But, typically, there is no
attempt in the book to substantiate such a crucial assumption with even
rudimentary empirical data. In chapter 7, where the authors claim to be
presenting the empirical picture corresponding to ‘metropolitan demand
on tropical landmass’, they carefully stay clear of data pertaining to two of
their cardinal assumptions, that these commodities are produced by petty
producers and that tropical land mass is fully used up. If the authors had conceived
their theory to follow from reality, they would have checked the
validity of these two assumptions before
presenting them. Their approach
is the opposite here, these assumptions seem to be tailor made to make their theory of
imperialism real and are in need of no further validation!
So,
how, according to the
Patnaiks, is a rise in the price of these commodities going to effect the
stability of metropolitan economy?
“Money
constitutes not only a medium of circulation, but also a form in which wealth
is held. Indeed, even in playing its medium of circulation role, money
simultaneously plays the role of being a form of wealth-holding… But the role
of money as a form of wealth-holding, which in real life it is, gets threatened
if its value is expected to fall vis-à-vis commodities, i.e., if wealth-holders
expect inflation to occur in commodity prices. In such a case they would be
tempted to shift from holding money to holding commodities.”[31]
Such
a shift from holding money to holding commodities, which arises because the
holders are not sure about the former’s value, will destroy the value of money
in the core, according to the Patnaiks. That is catastrophic for metropolitan
capitalism, as David Harvey remarks: “…prices
in the metropolis would skyrocket, the value of money in the metropolitan
capitalist economies would be destroyed, and the capitalist system would
crumble.”[32]
If
this is true, then it is an alarming situation for core capitalist countries. So,
how according to the Patnaiks, have the metropolitan capitalist core been warding off this threat to
the value of money? They argue that the primary mechanism for this has always
been ‘income deflation’ in the periphery.
“The commonest means of coping with the threat
historically has been through a reduction in the absorption of the products of
the tropical landmass within the periphery itself by the population of the
countries located on this very tropical landmass. And the primary instrument of
this has been the imposition of an “income deflation” upon them, through a
curtailment of their purchasing power so that, out of a relatively unchanging
output of the fixed tropical landmass, they are obliged to release more and
more goods for use in the metropolis. This happens either directly, in that the
same goods that are released from local mass absorption are then absorbed in
the metropolis; or it happens indirectly in that land that was previously
devoted to the production of goods for which mass demand declined because of
income deflation is now diverted to the production of other types of goods
demanded by the metropolis. In either case, any threat to the value of money in
the metropolis is warded off, and supplies are obtained from the tropical
landmass to meet metropolitan demand without the problem of increasing supply
price coming into play at all.”[33]
So the story is simple. The core capitalist countries
use “a set of non-market coercive political and economic mechanisms” to deflate
the income of peripheral populations so as to bring about a reduction in the
absorption of these commodities in the periphery. Since the absorbing power is
limited at the periphery, they will be forced to release more and more portion
of these commodities to the core. Or, because the demand for commodities used
in tropical areas are less owing to income deflation, periphery may shift to
production of commodities needed for the core. Either way, asserts the authors,
the excess demand in the core is met without any increase in the supply price
and the threat to the value of money is warded off. The authors restate the
argument later and in the process attempt
to define imperialism:
“To maintain the value of money and yet obtain its
requirements of products from the tropical landmass, metropolitan capital must
impose “income deflation” upon the people of the periphery, entailing
compression of their demand, so that commodities are snatched away from being
absorbed by them for use in the metropolis. The structural arrangement for such
income deflation is an essential component of imperialism and is as central
today as ever… Imperialism is concerned in short with the imposition of
income deflation by metropolitan capital on the people of the periphery in
order to squeeze out larger and larger supplies of a range of commodities
required in the metropolis, without bringing into play the problem of
increasing supply price that would threaten the value of money in the
metropolis.”[34]
So, according
to the Patnaiks, imperialism is not the highest stage of capitalism as
Lenin thought, nor is it necessitated by monopoly capitalism and the growth of
finance capital. It is merely the way in which capitalism deals with a
geographical asymmetry. The increasing demand for certain commodities which can
only be produced in the tropical countries can only be met in the core
temperate capitalist countries by an increased supply price. Such an increase
in the supply price leads to a decrease in the value of money and this decrease
would be catastrophic for capitalism. So it imposes income deflation in the
periphery which reduces the absorption of these commodities in the periphery
and makes them available to the core countries without an increase in price.
According to the Patnaiks, the set of non-market coercive mechanisms which are
used to impose income deflation is called imperialism. So, imperialism has been
a feature of capitalism throughout its existence and is not a stage of
capitalism at all! It is very obvious that the Patnaiks’ theory attempts to completely
debunk the Leninist notion of imperialism; it also means that Marx’s analysis
of capitalism was at best partial because he never examined this mechanism of income
deflation which has been a structural component of capitalism from the very
beginning. This is how the Patnaiks disprove Lenin and improve Marx!
How is it that this income deflation is imposed on the
periphery? The authors distinguish between two techniques of income deflation.
The first one is to impose it with the help of the state and the second one is
to effect ‘spontaneous’ income deflation. Their relative importance have
changed from colonial to neoliberal imperialism.
“In the colonial period the chief instrument of the
former was the colonial system of taxation, which, for much of the period, fell
heavily upon the peasantry… The “spontaneous” income deflation in the colonial
period, by contrast, arose from the fact of “deindustrialization”[35]
What about now?
“Income deflation of the colonial period had a
directness. A similar process occurs in a more indirect manner under
neoliberalism. Public finance in a neoliberal regime takes the form of keeping
the fiscal deficit controlled while giving tax concessions to the domestic and
foreign corporate- financial elements. This necessarily entails either a
rise in taxation upon other classes or a reduction in government expenditure
that would have otherwise put purchasing power in their hands. What fiscal
policy achieves, therefore, is a redistribution of purchasing power from the
other classes to the domestic and foreign corporate financial elements in the
country. Since the “propensity” to absorb tropical goods per unit of income in
the hands of these corporate financial elements is lower than the corresponding
propensity of the other classes, such redistribution has the effect ceteris
paribus of reducing the domestic absorption of tropical products within the
periphery.”[36]
So, fiscal policy is the main mechanism which is used
by the neoliberal state to impose income deflation. Purchasing power is robbed
from the people of the periphery mainly by two means: increase in taxes and
reduction in government expenditure. So it emerges from Patnaiks’ theory that
neoliberalism resorts to fiscal prudence primarily in order to deflate the
purchasing power of people in the periphery. This is completely at odds with
the prevailing Marxist analysis of the growth of neoliberalism and why it
resorts to fiscal prudence. The crisis of post war welfare capitalism along
with increasing liquidity and severe reduction of profitable investment
opportunities because of the fall of the rate of profit in advanced capitalist
countries prompted the growth of cut throat neoliberalism. One of the main
characteristics of neoliberalism was its propensity to find (or to create, if
it cannot be found) investment opportunities around the globe which led to the
opening up of the whole world to metropolitan capital. In this context,
reduction in government expenditure has a very important role to play. It would
open up sectors which were the monopoly of state to private capital, both
domestic and international, thereby giving them new and profitable investment
opportunities. Likewise, the transfer of the burden of taxation from the big
bourgeoisie to the toiling class is a desperate effort by the state to keep
these investments profitable. So these mechanisms, from a Marxist point of
view, are desperate attempts by the bourgeois to perpetuate and to expand
capitalist relations. But the authors do not consider these mechanisms as part
of capitalism’s effort to stay afloat by expanding capitalist relations to
newer and newer areas and to preserve profit margins in existing ones. Instead,
they consider these mechanisms as prompted by capitalism’s need to deflate the
income of the periphery so as to keep the price of tropical commodities and
value of money under check. Their theory is indeed sui generis!
The difference between Marxist approach and that of
the Patnaiks’ to the same phenomenon can be explained with the help of an example. It is a very well
documented fact that the neoliberal state withdraws itself from the health and
education sectors leaving the toiling population to the mercy of private
hospitals and private educational institutions. This withdrawal means that
common people have to spend much more on education and health care than what
they would have spent previously.
This would definitely curtail their purchasing power drastically, that is true.
But the Patnaiks elevate this effect to the main motivation itself of fiscal
prudence under neoliberalism. They argue that curtailing the purchasing power
of majority of the population is itself the aim of these measures and that this
is done for maintaining the value of money in the metropolis. This, they
declare, is what imperialism is all about! In contrast to this rather
far-fetched conspiracy theory, Marxism sees the withdrawal of state from
these sectors as prompted by the need for bringing them under capitalist
relations. There are two aspects to this withdrawal. The state withdraws from
capital intensive large scale sectors as the bourgeoisie has acquired the
economic and political clout to manage these sectors; in fact they are keen to
make a foray into these sectors as they know that there are large profits to be
had. International capital is also enthusiastic about this withdrawal as they
also see their chance to invest in, or even to capture, these sectors. The
second aspect is the withdrawal from social services like education, health,
communication and the discontinuation of various types of subsidies in food and
agriculture. These have a common aim; to facilitate the expansion of capitalism
into these areas and to change them into profit making businesses. This follows
directly from the basic characteristic of capitalism to bring anything and
everything under capital-wage labour relationship and to suck out surplus
value. This expansion of capitalism to service sector was necessitated by the
dropping rate of profit worldwide in the manufacturing and industrial sectors.
Thus, the withdrawal of the neoliberal state from health care is aimed at
opening up the health care sector to private capital and to allow it to make
profit from this sector too. It is not directly aimed at pauperising the
population, its primary motivation is to facilitate capitalist takeover of
everything from health to education, sport to poetry and from love to death. In their theory, the Patnaiks perform
a sleight of hand to turn the effect into essence and then christens it imperialism.
Impossibility of Land Augmentation According to Patnaiks
Core capitalism would have been spared all these
devious plots of imposing income deflation on the periphery if the metropolitan
demand for tropical commodities could
have been met just by producing more of these commodities. In short,
imperialism, as the Patnaiks define it, would have been unnecessary for
capitalism if the production of these commodities could be increased. This can
be done by two ways; either by bringing more and more land under cultivation or
by increasing the productivity of already cultivated land. The former course is
closed to history as the Patnaiks have, in the beginning of their analysis
itself, assumed that the “tropical landmass is more or less fully
used up”. Reality, I am sure, will stay clear of the course that has
been assumed by the Patnaiks as not possible. So that leaves only one option to avoid imperialism; increase in production of these
commodities by land augmentation. But this time the Patnaiks do not wish
away the problem by making an assumption, instead they tells us why land
augmentation was not possible under colonialism and why it is
impossible under neoliberalism.
Patnaiks contend that land augmentation, which they
define as “increase in output per natural unit of land”, requires “appropriate
water availability, better farm practices, high-yielding varieties of seeds,
heavier dosages of fertilizer use, and other such measures” which are
impossible without “state action in the form of investment in public
irrigation works; investment in research and development; a public extension
service network to make the results of research available to peasants; and
assured profits to peasants so that they can embark on the adoption of these
new land- augmenting farm practices”. In addition to these assertive state
measures, it also needs “land reforms that break the hold of landlordism and
the “rent barrier” to which it gives rise and which reduces the incentives
on the part of both the landlords and the tenants to introduce better farm
practices”. In short, according to the Patnaiks, proactive state support is
essential for land augmentation to take place. They further argue that such
state support was not forthcoming in colonial times, because “when tax
revenue was used as a means of siphoning off the surplus from the colonies to
the metropolis … hardly any resources were left for the state to undertake any
investment in irrigation, let alone in research and development for improving
agricultural practices”. The colonial state was also incapable of carrying
out radical land reforms since “the whole colonial regime needed the support
of landlords and local feudal elements”. The book argues that, due to the
above mentioned reasons, land augmentation never materialised during the
colonial era and capitalism had to resort to imperialism to deflate the income
of the periphery to make sure that the prices of tropical commodities did not go up. But what about
the post-colonial era, especially the neoliberal one?
“…the neoliberal state works directly and
exclusively in the interests of international finance capital, which is the
lead actor in the current epoch. The state acting directly and exclusively in
the interests of the lead actor of the world capitalism of the time is what
capitalism in its “spontaneity” demands. This precludes “land augmentation” as
a means of coping with the threat of increasing supply price of products of the
tropical landmass to the value of money in the metropolis.”[37]
Or, in other words,
“Since land- augmenting investment can be done
primarily by the state located on such land mass, and since state activism in
undertaking investment is typically frowned upon by capital (which prefers
“sound finance”), the supply of such goods cannot be augmented, ceteris paribus
to match the growing demands of metropolitan capital, as accumulation is
undertaken.”[38]
Hence, according to the authors, what rules out land
augmentation in neoliberal times is the character of the state which prefers
‘sound finance’ over state activism and professes the ‘withdrawal of state’. Hence,
imperialism remains the only option for capitalism in neoliberal times too for
protecting the value of money in the core. But these arguments immediately beg
many questions. Why should state support for peasant agriculture be the
predominant mechanism for land augmentation, why not the growth of capitalist
agriculture? The growth of capitalism in agriculture, at the expense of peasant
farming, will definitely have a land augmenting effect as it will be forced to
bring in large scale mechanised farming practices. But the authors argue that
such a shift to capitalism in agriculture was prevented in colonial times due
to the ‘rent barrier’; the landlords were prevented from moving to capitalist
farming because of the high rents which prevailed.
“…the landlords themselves were also hamstrung by
this “rent barrier,” which can be understood as follows. Any yield-raising
investment on land would typically require the resumption of the land from
petty tenants for direct cultivation by hired labour so that the landlords
could be sure of actually getting the benefits of such investment. But in such
a case, the investment that the landlord now had to make, had to earn not only
the going average rate of return on capital (in its alternative uses), but an
additional amount to cover the rent foregone. The higher the rent per unit area
the greater of course was this additional amount that had to be earned, which
meant that the high rents that actually prevailed as a consequence of colonial
deindustrialization erected a formidable barrier against land-augmenting technological
change, over and above the factor of state apathy mentioned earlier.”[39]
Because de-industrialisation of the country was not
accompanied or even followed by modern industrialisation in the earnest, the
rent on the land increased and this became a barrier for the shift to
capitalism in agriculture. But this does not explain why such a shift was not
possible in the years of welfare economy after independence or why it is not
possible now, under neoliberalism. What is at stake here is obvious, if such a
shift to capitalist agriculture is a possibility, then there is no need for
imperialist practices (as they are defined by the authors). The authors
understand this perfectly well and hence tries to hush the matter up by providing
reasons which are, at best, amusing. We shall encounter them later in this
article in the critique
of the Patnaiks’ theory.
Main Aspects of the Patnaiks’ Theory of Imperialism
We shall let the authors themselves sum up the whole argument.
“The argument presented until now can be restated
as follows. Capitalism cannot do without a whole range of goods produced by
peasants located in the tropical and subtropical areas that have a fixed
landmass - goods that either cannot ever be produced in temperate lands or
cannot ever be produced in adequate volumes. As the ex-ante demand for such
goods increases with capital accumulation, it cannot be met by increased output
from this fixed landmass without threatening the value of money in the
metropolis because of the increasing supply price of such output at any
given money wage rate. If land- augmenting investment and land-augmenting
technological change could occur in the tropical periphery for raising this
output, then increasing supply price could be kept in abeyance. But that
requires a relationship between the capitalist state (which has to play a
crucial role for such change) and the peasantry, which, other than a brief
period of dirigisme in the postcolonial era, simply cannot exist: the tendency
under capitalism is to pursue inter alia a fiscal policy characterized by
“sound finance” that precludes state activism in this regard.
As a result, this ex ante excess demand for tropical
and subtropical goods is met by the imposition of income deflation upon the
periphery itself, in order to squeeze out larger supplies from a given
output at the expense of local absorption. The alternative route of a profit
inflation combined with exchange rate depreciation in the periphery threatens
the value of money within the periphery and is unsustainable; besides, it does
not remove the threat to the value of money in the metropolis, apart from
arousing political opposition from the metropolitan working class. An income
deflation upon the workers in the metropolis itself is unlikely ever to be
imposed, if it is imposed at all, to an extent that does away with the need for
income deflation on the working people in the periphery. In short, squeezing
local absorption in the periphery to meet the demands of capital accumulation
in the metropolis is an essential feature of capitalism, and this, far from
being obviated by capital accumulation (and the development of capitalism)
within the periphery, only makes the problem even more serious. Reducing
such local absorption by poor populations through income deflation is the
essence of imperialism.”[40]
So, let us list the main aspects of the theory of
imperialism presented by the Patnaiks.
- Geographical asymmetry between the temperate and tropical zones with respect to the capacity of production of certain commodities.
- These tropical commodities are produced by peasants or by petty producers.
- The tropical land mass is more or less fully used up.
- Increasing supply price of these commodities because of increase in demand due to capital accumulation.
- This increase threatens the value of money in the core and the periphery.
- Impossibility of land augmentation in the periphery for raising the output of these commodities.
- Imposing income deflation upon the periphery with an eye to reduce local absorption of these commodities and making them available to the core at non-increasing price as the only way to protect the value of money; this is the ‘essence’ of imperialism.
3. David Harvey’s Critique
David Harvey, in his commentary which is included in
the book itself, has offered a critique of the theory. Even though his critique
makes no effort to trace the main motivations of presenting such an obviously
flawed theory or to link the theory to the reformist, social democratic
politics professed by the academic left in India, it raises some pertinent
questions. Hence, we shall have a
quick look at the main points of this critique.
Harvey on Looseness of Definitions
Harvey starts by pointing out the vagueness in the
definition of ‘tropical landmass’ in the book.
“There is, however, a damaging looseness in the way
they articulate this physical proposition… This would not matter were it not
for the fact that it is the very specific productive capacities of the tropical
landmass that grounds what their theory of imperialism is all about.”[41]
Harvey has a valid point here, especially given the
fact that the whole theory bases itself on the asymmetrical productive
capacities of the ‘tropical’ and ‘temperate’ land masses. If the claim is that
there is an asymmetry between tropical and temperate land masses, the least
that should be done is to properly enlighten us as to what is temperate and what is tropical. So it
is only fair that one would expect this ‘tropical landmass’ to be properly
defined. As Harvey asks,
“So where this “tropical landmass” and what are the
climatic conditions that create the monopoly over the supply of certain
agricultural inputs to metropolitan capitalism? Again, there is a lot of
looseness of definition here. Sometimes the Patnaiks talk exclusively about
tropical regions, while elsewhere they include the subtropics. So where is this
region exactly and what are its geographical characteristics?”[42]
Harvey points out the difficulties in neatly
categorising nations as tropical or temperate and the difficulties that this
will cause to Patnaiks’ theory of imperialism. Harvey is right when he says
that “There is some awkwardness in this classification because many states
(like China, Brazil, Argentina, Mexico, the United States, and even India
itself) straddle climatic zones, and the trading patterns occurring between
countries and currency blocks do not correspond to climatic configurations.
This is particularly the case in China, where a vast subtropical southern zone
contrasts with a temperate continental climate north of the Yangtze River.”[43] It is abundantly clear
from this short discussion itself that the tropics vs temperate dualism,
utilised by the Patnaiks, is hardly an air tight basis for a theory of
imperialism. Contrast this to Lenin’s analysis of imperialism which rests on the rock solid basis of
an analysis of the monopoly stage of capitalism. But it is just ‘conjunctural’
and therefore irrelevant as far as the Patnaiks are concerned. It is normal for us to expect that the Patnaiks would
clarify their idea about the tropical zone in their response to Harvey’s
commentary. But instead they arrogantly dismiss it with a gem of an obfuscating argument.
“We do not enter into definitions of what is north
and what is south, what is the centre and what is the periphery—matters with
which Harvey makes much play. As Joan Robinson famously remarked, it is
possible to define a point in mathematics in one sentence, but we cannot so
define an elephant; it hardly matters, however, for we know an elephant when we
see it—unless we happen to be blind.”[44]
This is, it has to be said, a particularly convincing
reply! Tropics are like elephants, for we shall know a tropical landmass when
we see it!!!
Is the Tropical Landmass Fully Used Up?
Harvey then swiftly proceeds to his next query.
“Is all the land in the tropical landmass already
used up? The answer is a resounding “no.” There is abundant “open land” in
sub-Saharan Africa, and the recent pace of invasion of Amazonia by the soybean
planters, the cattle interests, and the loggers defines a vigorous frontier of
conversion of tropical rainforests to commercial agriculture”[45]
Harvey asserts that the claim ‘tropical landmass is
more or less fully used up’ is not true, there is a movement towards that
scenario, but we are nowhere near it now. This is a serious problem for the
Patnaiks as they have based their theory on the assumption (more of a
pious wish) that increasing demand for tropical products cannot be met by
simply bringing more land into cultivation. If it is not, it is not clear why
income deflation, and with it imperialism is needed! Moreover, it is amusing
to see that the Patnaiks’ have used the above assumption not just to the
neoliberal times, but to the colonial one too. This is so since their
theory is qualitatively the same for colonial and neoliberal times, the only
difference is in the modus operandi of the core states in imposing
income deflation. To say that metropolitan states needed to impose income
deflation on the periphery in 1850 to ward off the threat to value of money
arising due to the increasing demand for tropical commodities, when they could
have just brought new land under the plough, is indeed amusing!
Geographical Determinism
By far the most serious objection that Harvey makes
against the Patnaiks’ theory is that it succumbs to “crude environmental
determinism”. He notes that, in spite of their claim “that the foundation of
their whole analysis lies in class relations”, their theory argues that
“these class relations play out across the immutable and fixed geographical
environment of the tropical landmass in such a way as to make its imperialist
domination and exploitation both necessary and inevitable to the survival of
capitalism”. Harvey is here alluding to the fact that the Patnaiks’ theory is
based on a strict and fixed opposition between temperate and tropical
geographical regions, the characteristics and production capacities of which do
not change in any qualitative way in the course of centuries[46]. What changes is merely
the way in which capitalism imposes income deflation to deal with this fixed
problem. As Harvey says, this means that,
“…the Patnaiks here choose to follow a whole line of
economists who conceive of “geography” in purely “natural” physical and
immutable biotic terms as if the social production of space and the long
history of human modifications of environments do not matter. Our relevant
geographical environment has in large measure been modified and produced by
human action and, particularly over the last few centuries, by capitalist
imperatives… The tropical landmass as it is now constituted is completely
different to that of the last century… Geography, I insist, is far more than a
bunch of data about climate and soil types, and I object strenuously to the
Patnaiks’ antiquarian conception of it”[47]
This fixity and immutability of concepts
is a characteristic of the whole theory put forward by the Patnaiks and is not
limited to their analysis of geography. As we have seen before, the Patnaiks’
theory premises that the tropical landmass has been fully used up from the
colonial times itself and that it remains so to this day. No effort what so
ever is made in the book to study the pattern of land usage in backward
capitalist countries across the world. Furthermore, Patnaiks’ theory, to be plausible, needs the tropical
commodities to be produced by peasants or petty producers. They argue this to
be the case, and again, makes no effort to investigate the possible disintegration
of the material basis of peasant agriculture and petty production. This is
especially surprising because that is the natural course followed as capitalism
matures. Instead, they advance speculative arguments to try and prove that
these commodities shall continue to be produced through petty production. This
fascination with fixity and immutability, this reluctance to
engage with dynamics, may it be of geography, tropical land usage or
petty production, has its roots in the non-dialectical nature of the Patnaiks’
analysis. We shall have more to say about this later when we analyse their
method in detail.
In their response, the Patnaiks try to defend
themselves from the charge of ‘geographical determinism’ by shifting the
goalposts; that is, by shifting the stress of their theory from geography to
economics!
“Central to our theory is not some geographical
determinism but the concept of increasing supply price, which implies an
undermining of the value of money under capitalism, and reflects the fact that
certain commodities under certain circumstances are producible only at an
increasing supply price - a fact that no economist can deny and that even
Keynes underscored in his classic The Economic Consequences of the Peace.”[48]
If only the Patnaiks had informed us earlier itself
that their basic premise is ratified ‘even’ by Keynes Himself, we would not
have dared to entertain any doubts on their theory! It is very representative
of their class character that they are out to correct Marx, but consider Keynes
as the final word. In the response, they continue to disown the
geographical basis of their theory which they were stressing in the main text:
“Our theory of imperialism is about capitalism as
it behaves in the context of certain undeniable facts relating to production
possibilities of different regions. It is about capitalism not geography.”[49]
It takes much more than peppering the book with words
like ‘spontaneity’ to prove that the theory presented is about capitalism and
not geography. Granted, for argument sake, that imperialism according to the
Patnaiks theory, is not an inevitable product of geography. It arises from the
way in which capitalism tries to overcome a deprivation outside of it. But, is
it a consequence of the characteristics of capitalist mode of production? Does
it arise from the inherent contradictions of capitalism? Unlike Lenin’s
theory which tells us how imperialism grows out of capitalism’s unresolvable
contradictions, the Patnaiks’ theory reduces it to capitalism’s strategy
in dealing with a problem outside if it. They argue that the prime motivation
for the practice of imperialism does not come from inside capitalism but
from outside, from geography. The authors knows that this is a serious handicap
of their theory and tries to sidestep it by proposing that this strategy
itself is a structural relationship that characterises capitalism, alongside the
capital – wage labour one! Ingenious are the ways in which ‘academicians’ spin
out their theories, more so if they happen to be trying to thrust their petty
bourgeois illusions on the world.
4. Patnaiks’ Imperialism – A Critique
The Method
First, let’s cast a glance at the method employed by
the Patnaiks. In his generous forward to the book, fellow social democrat Akeel
Bilgrami praises Patnaiks’ method thus, “At each step of the argument, the book
considers a number of objections to the argument at that stage or considers
claims that are alternative to their own claims at that stage of the argument;
and it addresses these objections and alternatives before it moves to the next
step. This dialectical method…”. So, this is the dialectical method! Bilgrami,
true to his class loyalties, naively confuses objections with contradictions
here, and assume that dealing with a lot of (self-conjured) objections and
addressing each of them amounts to dialectics! If Marx had used this
‘dialectical’ method in his capital, his first sentence “The wealth of
societies in which the capitalist mode of production prevails appears as an
immense collection of commodities; the individual commodity appears as its
elementary form. Our investigation therefore begins with the analysis of the
commodity” would have been followed by the answers to the objections, why not money,
why not capital, why not factories, why commodity? Instead, Marx plunges into
the two contradictory aspects of commodity. A dialectical analysis of
imperialism would have tried to unearth its dynamics, whereas it is evident
that the Patnaiks are interested in its statics. The authors claim that
imperialism is an invariant structural aspect of capitalism. Even
if it were true, dialectics would have followed the dynamics of such invariance.
Materialist dialectics would have investigated the origin of imperialism in the
structural contradictions of the mode of production (that is exactly what Lenin
did) and not just pictured it as a strategy of capitalism with no
structural connection to its contradictions. The Patnaiks’ method, in spite of
their friend Bilgrami’s generous praise, is anything but dialectical.
This is immediately obvious when we try to wade
through its different aspects. For instance, in his commentary, Harvey
wonders,
“So where, then, do we find tropical and
subtropical land that can grow temperate region crops and is fully occupied
under conditions of non-capitalistic, peasant agrarian production? The best
answer I can come up with is much (but by no means all) of the Patnaiks’ India
(and perhaps the African Sahel zone). If all the tropical world were like
India, then they might have a case, but it is not.”[50]
I shall remark immediately that even if we take India,
the above assertions of the authors that Harvey alludes to are wrong! But
nevertheless it is clear, as Harvey says, that whenever they say tropics the
authors’ picture India. This is why when asked to ‘define’ the tropics,
Patnaiks’ had to evoke the elephants! Marx too wrote Capital mainly after a
thorough study of English capitalism, but the method employed was very
different. As Lukacs remarked,
“Marx never ‘generalised’ from particular
experiences limited in time and space. On the contrary – true to the methods of
genuine historical and political genius – he detected, both theoretically and
historically, in the microcosm of the English factory system, in its social
premises, its conditions and consequences, and in the historical trends which
both lead to, and in turn eventually threaten its development, precisely the
macrocosm of capitalist development as a whole.”[51]
It is precisely such uncritical generalisation of
particular experiences, which is the very opposite of dialectics, that
underlies the method of this book. Much of what the Patnaiks have to say about
the ‘tropics’ are fully invalid if we take Africa or even China. Such
generalisation of the Indian experience is bound to give wrong results. Here,
it is exacerbated by the fact that their interpretation of even that particular
Indian experience is wrong!
We have already seen that the Patnaiks’ basic argument
is that capitalism is characterised by two structural relationships. One, the
capital – wage labour relationship, and two, imperialism. Marx, in spite of
studying capitalism in the heydays of colonialism (which is, according to the
Patnaiks, imperialism in colonial times and nothing more) based his study only
on the first relationship. Marx studied colonialism deeply and wrote about it profusely; so, if he did not
accord colonialism the status of a basic structural aspect of
capitalism, it was because he was convinced it did not belong there. This is
clear from his plan of study which he alludes to in Grundrisse:
“The order obviously has to be (1) the general
abstract determinations which obtain more or less in all forms of society… (2)
the categories which make up the inner structure of bourgeois society, and on
which the fundamental classes rest, capital, wage labour and landed property.
Their inter-relation. Town and country. The three great social classes.
Exchange between them. Circulation, credit system (private). (3) Concentration
of bourgeois society in the form of the state – viewed in relation to itself.
The ‘unproductive’ classes. Taxes, state debt, public credit. The population.
The colonies. Emigration. (4) The international relations of production. International
division of labour. International exchange. Export and import. Rate of
exchange. (5) The world market and crisis.”[52]
It becomes clear from this plan, and also from
his finished works, that Marx envisioned the questions of colonialism,
international relations of production, international exchange and world market
to be the derivatives of “the basic categories which make up the inner
structure of bourgeois society”. The Patnaiks’ are definitely not happy with
this plan and wants imperialism to be made a ‘basic category’ of
capitalism. This amounts to a complete revision of Marxism, even though they
try to hide this fact as well as they can in the book.
Imperialism as a ‘Structural Relationship’ that
Characterises Capitalism
We have already seen how the Patnaiks define
imperialism as “… a certain structural relationship that characterises
capitalism but that, surprisingly, has received very little attention until now
…in addition to the capital – wage labour relationship, capitalism is
characterised by an additional structural relationship, and “imperialism”
refers to that structural relationship”. It is very instructive to study
the diametrically opposed ways in which Marx arrives at capital – wage labour
relationship and in which the Patnaiks arrive at imperialism, which they
contend is an additional structural relationship which characterises
capitalism. The essence of Marx’s method is captured by Ernest Mandel in his
celebrated introduction to Marx’s Capital, vol. 1.
“It is no accident that Marx starts Capital Volume
1 with an analysis neither of ‘the capitalist mode of production’, nor of
capital, nor of wage labour, nor even of the relations between wage labour
and capital. For it is impossible to analyse any of these basic concepts or
categories – which corresponds to the basic structure of capitalist society –
scientifically, totally and adequately without a previous analysis of value,
exchange value and surplus value. But these latter categories in turn hinge
upon an analysis of the commodity and commodity producing labour.” [53]
So, the relationship between wage labour and capital,
which is a basic structural element of capitalism, unfolds ‘scientifically,
totally and adequately’ from an analysis of commodity and commodity producing
labour. The exploitation immanent in the capital – wage labour relationship
reveals itself only upon a dialectical analysis which starts from commodity. In
Marx’s analysis, this structural relationship between wage labour and capital
is not a given, not even a starting point of analysis, but is the ‘material
concrete’ which is reproduced by the analysis of elementary material phenomenon
– the commodity. Thus, while in Marx’s analysis, the wage labour – capital
relationship emerges from the dialectical analysis of the commodity, the
Patnaiks’ analysis posits imperialism as another structural relationship
characterising capitalism, at par with wage labour – capital relationship, in a rather casual manner. The
Patnaiks’ analysis does not give us any clue as to how this second structural
relationship emerges, it is obvious that it does not unfold from an analysis of
the basic Marxian categories of capitalism.
The Patnaiks seems to suggest at many places in the
book that imperialism emerges out of the ‘spontaneous’ way in which capitalism
deals with geographical asymmetry. As they say towards the beginning of their
work, “… its essence lies in the fact that capitalism, … must, in its
‘spontaneous’ operation, act in ways that tends to immiserate the traditional
petty producers of the third world”. With this assertion, the situation
becomes amusing. Imperialism, assert the Patnaiks, is one of the two basic
structural aspects of capitalism, the other one being the capital – wage labour
relationship. Then, these should determine the character of capitalism as a
social mode of production. In particular, capitalism’s ‘spontaneity’, which the
authors evoke repeatedly in this work, should emerge from these structural
characteristics. So, capitalism’s ‘spontaneity’ is at least partly determined
by imperialism as one of the structural characteristic of capitalism. But in
the book, the Patnaiks assert that it is this ‘spontaneity’ of capitalism that
leads to imperialism! The book describes capitalism’s unplanned and spontaneous
nature as the biggest impediment to the solution of the geographical
asymmetries by non-imperialist means. So, capitalist spontaneity, which is
partly caused by imperialism, is identified by the Patnaiks as the main cause
for imperialism! When Proudhon put forward the thesis that ‘property is
theft’, Marx characterised it as eating one’s own tail because theft cannot be
defined without recourse to the idea of property. The Patnaiks’ logic belongs
to the same league; imperialism is a structural element of capitalism, so
capitalism’s ‘spontaneity is determined by it, this spontaneity is the basic
driving cause of imperialism!
The Patnaiks’ Love Story with Petty Producers
We have already seen how the Patnaiks adamantly
maintains that tropical products are produced by petty producers. When it comes
to products of tropical landmass, the authors assert that they are produced
almost exclusively by peasants. It is as if they are mortified at the prospect
of having no one whose income can be deflated! We have seen how they theorise
the persistence of petty agricultural production in the periphery in colonial
times. The colonial regime’s refusal to undertake any investment in irrigation
or in research and development for improving agricultural practices coupled
with their inability to carry out land reforms were identified as reasons for
this. Moreover, the ‘rent-barrier’, according to the Patnaiks, acted as a major
hindrance to modernising agriculture during the colonial era. But after
independence, the Patnaiks note that there were efforts from the newly
independent states to promote the growth of capitalist agriculture.
“While the colonial period saw little land
augmentation, there was a change in this respect after decolonization. The
dirigiste regimes that came to power as legatees of the anticolonial struggles
were committed in a sense to providing some relief to the peasantry. While they
by and large eschewed any radical land redistribution (except in East Asia
under American occupation as a means of breaking the power of Japanese
landlords, or where Communist regimes came to power), they did carry out land
reforms up to a point, usually to facilitate a transition to capitalist
farming, which would typically be an admixture of both peasant capitalism and
landlord capitalism. Such measures included giving ownership rights to rich
tenants who could then take to capitalist agriculture. Additionally, the
dirigiste regimes did undertake several important measures, such as protecting
agriculture against world market price fluctuations, providing subsidized
credit and other inputs, carrying out some research and development, setting up
a wide extension network, investing in irrigation, and providing assured
remunerative prices. No doubt the bulk of the benefits of these measures
accrued to the emerging capitalist class in the countryside, but some also went
to other sections of the peasantry.” [54]
So, the authors concede that the efforts of the
bourgeois welfare state to promote capitalism in agriculture did bear some
fruits. The state’s protection against price fluctuations, subsidies and
credits that it provided, research and development, investments in irrigation
and remunerative prices, did lead, according to the Patnaiks, to the
constitution of an “emerging capitalist class in the countryside”. So the first
impediment in the colonial era, namely the absence of state support, was
overcome. What about the second hindrance, the ‘rent barrier’? They assert that
this was overcome following the ‘green revolution’.
“At any rate, owing to the sharp rise in yield
permitted by “green revolution” technology, the rent barrier was overcome, and
land augmentation did occur. As a result, there was a considerable increase in
agricultural output under the dirigiste regimes, even in countries with fixed
and fully utilized tropical landmasses, compared to the colonial period.” [55]
The two major barriers for the development of
capitalism in agriculture, namely, the absence of infrastructure in irrigation
and the ‘rent barrier’, both were overcome during the dirigisme regime itself,
says the Patnaiks. But they go on to argue that under the neoliberal state, the
situation is different.
“…the neoliberal state curtails “land-augmenting”
expenditure and investment, just as it curtails welfare expenditures and
transfer payments to the poor. At the same time, subsidies to the peasants are
cut, cheap credit is no longer made available, input prices are raised, public
extension services dwindle, protection against world market price fluctuations
is removed, and even procurement operation at assured remunerative prices is
wound up (since it also falls foul of World Trade Organization rules). “Land
augmentation” therefore, as had been the case in colonial times, takes a back
seat… It is also not surprising that large numbers of peasants find even
“simple reproduction” impossible to carry on. In countries like India they are
leaving agriculture in considerable numbers and are also resorting to large-
scale suicides (over 240,000 peasant suicides have occurred in India over the
first decade and half of the present century)” [56]
Because of their training as bourgeois academicians,
the Patnaiks cannot help presenting the facts as they are, but owing to their
petty bourgeois orientation their interpretation of these facts are almost
always regressive. This is exactly because “in their minds they do not get
beyond the limits that the latter (petty bourgeois) do not get beyond in life”,
as Marx so succinctly observed. This present discussion is an excellent example
of this. They correctly locate the barriers that existed in the path of the
development of capitalism in colonial India, they also detail the ways in which
these barriers were overcome by the assertive action of the welfare state which
lead to the development of capitalism in Indian agriculture, albeit that of a
Junker variety. They also see what is happening in neoliberal era when support
measures are being removed one by one. All these are correct and incisive, but
what follows is horrendous petty theorising of the petty bourgeois:
“…the neoliberal state works directly and exclusively
in the interests of international finance capital, which is the lead actor in
the current epoch. The state acting directly and exclusively in the interests
of the lead actor of the world capitalism of the time is what capitalism in its
“spontaneity” demands. This precludes “land augmentation” as a means of coping
with the threat of increasing supply price of products of the tropical landmass
to the value of money in the metropolis.” [57]
The Patnaiks vehemently refuses to draw conclusions
which are staring at their faces from their own arguments. Their logic is a
very good example of evasion and proceeds like this: land augmentation and
growth of capitalism in agriculture were prevented in colonial times by the
absence of state support and rent barrier. But, after independence, both of
these were reversed under the watch of the post-colonial welfare states. State
support was forth coming and green revolution accounted for the rent barrier.
Capitalist growth and land augmentation began to occur during this phase in the
periphery. This was followed by the neoliberal era in which the return of the
dogma of fiscal prudence meant that state support was again withheld. From
this, the Patnaiks reason that land augmentation is no longer possible under
neoliberalism. But they carefully evade the central question here: what
about the growth of capitalism in agriculture which they themselves theorise to
have commenced during the welfare state regime? One would expect this growth to
intensify in the neoliberal phase because of the destruction of peasants and
petty producers following the withdrawal of state support and subsidies. In
that case, there can be capitalism induced land augmentation too. The Patnaiks
refuse to engage with this question at all in the book and instead hurriedly
concludes that as the neoliberal state cannot undertake state funding land augmentation
is ruled out. By out rightly refusing to engage with the issue of growth and
spread of capitalism, they maintain that the products needed by the core are
produced exclusively by petty producers in the periphery. God only knows what
happened to capitalist production which the authors themselves conceded had
grown in post-colonial era. I guess it evaporated, unable to withstand the heat
of Patnaiks’ theorising. There is no other plausible reason for the sudden
disappearance of capitalism!
What is the primary conclusion to be drawn from their
own analysis, which the authors are unable to draw because of their class
orientation, and from which they are steering clear? It is this: The welfare state had made sure that
the important barriers to the growth of capitalism in peripheral countries were
overcome. Capitalist agriculture was fast beginning to stand on its feet. Under
these circumstances, the neoliberal rolling back of state interference can only
expedite the shift towards capitalism as it makes peasant agriculture
untenable. The roll back of dirigiste measures which Patnaik detail above show
exactly that they are specifically aimed at finishing off peasant agriculture.
And these measures are having the desired effect, they are making sure that
even simple reproduction is impossible for the peasants, as noted by the
Patnaiks themselves. This is an expected step from the bourgeois state to help
the bourgeoisie to finish off petty production in every field. And in this
sense, in Marxist – Leninist terms, they are objectively progressive and have
to be politically approached in a dialectical manner. Petty bourgeois Patnaiks
cannot follow this approach as it will directly lead them to revolutionary
conclusions. To avoid these conclusions, they refuse to even engage with the
obvious and pertinent questions which their own analysis throws up. Hence their
absolute refusal to trace the further route of capitalist agriculture in
neoliberal era.
As the Patnaiks document emotionally, petty production
is being destroyed by the actions of the Indian state, but what is happening to
the capitalist production? Their analysis does not even pose this question.
Instead, they conclude that the refusal to continue land augmenting measures is
specifically followed at the behest of international finance capital for coping
with the threat of increasing supply price by imposing income deflation on
petty producers. Here, the Patnaiks are performing a brilliant sleight of hand.
They claim that the withdrawal of state is at the direct behest of core
capitalism and is aimed at imposing income deflation on petty producers and
thus to preserve the value of money, when the truth is that it is done by the
bourgeois state to crush petty production by withdrawing all support structures
that propped it up and by exposing it to the vagaries of the competitive
market. This is done to aid the growth of capitalism (not only in agriculture,
but in all fields). International finance capital, conscious of the lack of
investing opportunities in the core due to the fast declining rate of profit,
is bent upon the creation of investment opportunities in the third world, for
which it needs the unbridled growth of capitalist relations in every field. So,
normally, it pushes for such measures in the third world states. The result of
all this is the growth of capitalism and the destruction of petty production in
all areas (even in areas such as education, health, human relations etc.). The
peasants and other petty producers are being destroyed because of this, but
such destruction is not aimed at decreasing their purchasing power, decrease in
purchasing power is the result of their destruction which was done to expedite
the growth and reach of capitalism. The Patnaiks know fully well that
Marxism sees such destruction of petty production as objectively unavoidable
and progressive and desists from advancing any argument for its reversal. Defining
imperialism the way they do allow them to picture this destruction of petty
production as a part of the imperialist plot for income deflation, rather than
as a consequence of growth of capitalism. Thus they get to argue, as they did
before, that such destruction is very different from that which happened in Europe
during the heydays of capitalism. In this manner, they carve out space to argue
for the preservation of petty production and the petty bourgeois which
revolutionary Marxism does not allow them to do. Petty production has to be preserved as a
part of the fight against imperialism because what we are seeing in peripheral
economies is the destruction of petty production by imperialism for reducing
the periphery’s purchasing power. Petty bourgeois aims have become miraculously
progressive! Now the Marxist-Leninist stand on destruction of petty bourgeois
can conveniently be ignored. It is in this sense that this article maintained
at the beginning itself that the Patnaiks’ theory of imperialism is tailor made
to render the petty bourgeois social
democratic politics of the left progressive.
To give their argument further weight, the Patnaiks
detail the differential treatment meted out to the peasantry in core and
peripheral areas.
“One can see the impact of capitalism on the
pre-capitalist petty producers, especially the peasantry, in terms of two
sharply contrasting scenarios. In the heartland of capitalism, namely within
the metropolis itself where capitalism first developed, the peasantry was
largely destroyed as a class (with certain obvious exceptions like France where
it survived but kept reducing in relative size over time); the erstwhile
peasants along with other segments of the workforce, including displaced
artisans, who were not absorbed by capitalist activities at home, migrated to
the temperate regions of white settlement… But in lands far from the cold
temperate metropolis, the dispossession of local petty producers in the
tropical and subtropical regions was not accompanied by a destruction of the
peasantry as a class. It was effected through the setting up of “colonies of
conquest,” to which relatively little migration took place from the metropolis.
The object of the expropriation of peasants in such colonies of conquest was
not to introduce capitalist agriculture in lieu of peasant agriculture. On the
contrary, the peasantry in these countries lingered on, even when losing its
rights over land and being reduced to the status of inferior tenants.” [58]
Here again, they strictly restrict their analysis to
the colonial times in which it is correct to maintain that the destruction of
peasantry followed different paths in the core capitalist countries and the
colonies. The reader yearns to know what happened after that, after the
dirigiste regimes lead to the growth of capitalism and after neoliberal reforms
took over. Did the shift to capitalist agriculture begin in the earnest in the
post-colonial societies too, or was there any new movement? But the Patnaiks
won’t oblige; in fact they can’t, because if they do, they will have to concede that the destruction of
petty production is fast progressing in post-colonial world in neoliberal era.
Then alas, whose income they shall deflate!
We have already seen that the Patnaiks evade the
question of further development of the destruction of petty production because
they want to ‘arrive’ at some different conclusions. For them, the destruction
of petty production in third world has nothing to do with the development of
capitalism here, instead it is the result of a devious plot etched by the
metropolitan capital, a plot which they call imperialism. Thus we come to the
Patnaiks’ one main pet conclusion. In fact, their whole theory of imperialism
is devised so that this conclusion can be successfully drawn. Behold…
“The fact that big capital of the third world
itself is complicit in this process of undermining and squeezing the
traditional petty producers, viz., the peasants, craftsmen, fishermen artisans,
and so on—is not germane to the argument, just as the fact that
metropolitan capitalism also squeezes its own residual petty producers, not to
mention the workers directly employed by it, is not germane to the argument.
What is important is the fact of this compression of income and livelihoods
exercised by metropolitan capitalism upon the traditional petty producers of
the third world, especially of the tropics. This occurs for a very specific
reason and must be distinguished from the general tendency of capitalism to
destroy the basis of petty production everywhere.” [59]
So the destruction of petty producers in countries
like India is predominantly due to imperialism which should be distinguished
from general tendency to destroy petty production in capitalism. The latter is
progressive, but the former is not progressive and hence should be, and can be,
stopped and fought. Hurray… the petty bourgeois left can now talk about
stopping the destruction of petty production without a prick to their ‘Marxist’
soul, all due to the Patnaiks’ carefully crafted theory of imperialism! Further, the authors have also devised a very original strategy for
evading uncomfortable questions. Reading this para, one get the feeling that
Harvey got it exactly correct: “All such questions would be swept aside as ‘not
germane to the argument’, as happens throughout their text whenever they
encounter an awkward conundrum.”
The Benevolence of Capitalism!
We have already seen that the Patnaiks traces the ways
in which the barriers to development of capitalism in agriculture in the
periphery were more or less overcome in the welfare state interlude. They have
themselves explained how the peasantry is getting destroyed as a consequence of
the neoliberal reforms. Now a crucial question presents itself which even
academicians with the dexterity of Patnaiks shall find hard to evade. Even if
there is a problem of increasing supply price of tropical commodities which
leads to a threat to the value of money in the core, and even if it cannot be
circumvented by land augmentation due to the refusal of neoliberal state, can’t
such a land augmentation be brought about through development of capitalism in
agriculture? This shall definitely lead to a marked increase in the
agricultural yield and shall also push the state, even the neoliberal one, to
invest in agricultural infrastructure as now it is being done for the rural
bourgeoisie and not for the peasants. Patnaiks explain why the colonial state
did not resort to this route instead ‘chose’ the income deflation one.
“…wholesale appropriation of peasant lands for the
development of capitalism in the tropics, would have caused no land
augmentation per se and hence brought about the same result, viz., mass income
deflation in the periphery, which occurred anyway. But it would have brought
about this result in a far more violent form for capitalism, in a far more
socially and politically unsustainable form, than the actual forms of income
deflation that were resorted to.” [60]
The benevolence of capitalism!!! Such kind
heartedness! The same goodness of heart that Marx famously noted in Capital:
“If money, according to Augier, ‘comes into the world
with a congenital blood stain on one cheek’, capital comes dripping from head
to toe, from every pore, with blood and dirt”
And then again commented about in his writings on
colonialism:
“Has the
bourgeoisie ever done more? Has it ever effected a progress without dragging
individuals and people through blood and dirt, through misery and degradation?”
But suddenly, capitalism, in its colonialist avatar,
becomes so accommodating that it chose the painless route of income deflation
to the violent route of development of capitalism in the tropics, something
that it never even contemplated doing in its own backyard. I say we erect a
monument in honour of colonial capitalism’s kindness, and one, just besides it,
for the Patnaiks’ cunningness. To suggest that capitalism (in its
‘spontaneity’, of course) shall willingly forego a chance for its expansion
because it doesn’t want this process to be violent is to completely forget
capitalism’s history spanning half a millennium which is dipped in blood. The Patnaiks further tell us that, had the ‘development of capitalism
in the periphery’ route been taken, imperialism would have been unnecessary as
this would have solved the problems arising out of geographical asymmetry.
“No doubt, if capitalism had supplanted peasant
agriculture in the tropical lands, then the reluctance on the part of the
colonial (or semicolonial) state to undertake land-augmenting expenditure might
have been less, since the beneficiaries of such expenditure would have been not
tropical peasants but (realistically at the time) a group of capitalists
largely drawn from the metropolis itself. But, if there had been capitalism in
tropical agriculture, then the massive income deflation it would have meant in
the form of dispossession of the peasantry would have made it unnecessary for
the state to undertake any large- scale expenditure on land augmentation
anyway. This is because supplies from the tropics for the requirements of
metropolitan capitalism would have been available aplenty by this very fact of
dispossession and hence the extraordinarily massive income and demand deflation
that such dispossession would have entailed.” [61]
But, as we have seen, this route was not taken as
capitalism, in the illusionary form in which it appears in the authors’ minds,
abhors violent means. So,
“The capitalist sector’s demand for tropical
products therefore was met historically, and continues to be met today,
through an income deflation imposed on the periphery, even while retaining
broadly the framework of a peasant agriculture (notwithstanding the more
recent development of capitalism, both landlord capitalism and peasant
capitalism, at the margin, from within such agriculture).” [62]
Two questions readily emerge. One, even if, for the
sake of argument, one concedes the ridiculous point that metropolitan capital
shunned the ‘development of capitalism’ route in the periphery in colonial
times because it would have been too ‘violent’, it escapes me completely why it
would do the same in neo liberal era. Why on earth would it want to preserve
petty production now also and take the strenuous route of income deflation
rather than the development of capitalism route? Evidently because this income
deflation plot is only a figment of Patnaiks’ imagination and follows the
diktats of no one else but the Patnaiks; it takes the route that allow the
authors to argue that preserving petty production is a progressive act, simple!
Two, given the fact that their whole theory of imperialism rests on the premise
that tropical products are produced by petty producers and that capitalist
production is not the main mode, why are the authors not investigating the
consequences of this ‘recent’ development? What shall happen to the strategy of
income deflation when capitalist production takes over in tropics? Such an
analysis alone is capable of sketching the dynamics of the process the authors
claim is happening. They evidently don’t inquire into it as such an inquiry
will blow their carefully concocted
theory to pieces.
Spontaneous Choice or a Devious Plot?
The authors state, ad nauseam in their work, that income
deflation imposed on the periphery is a spontaneous process and not a planned
plot, it is the result of the ‘dark urges’ of capitalism. But, despite their
statements, their analysis suggests otherwise.
A good example for this is the Patnaiks’ argument on
core capitalism’s preference for income deflation of petty producers rather
than their complete pauperisation by the development of capitalism. We were
informed that this is because the latter course is too violent and
unsustainable. If we assume that Patnaiks’ argument is correct, then this is an
informed choice taken after weighing the pros and cons of each option. There is
nothing spontaneous about such a choice. Especially because, in its
spontaneity, capitalism would always choose to spread itself to facilitate
accumulation. Hence, this is a choice which is completely at odds with the
basic character of capital itself. This is one among the many instances in the
text at which the authors try to circumvent the difficulty to explain what
seems like a well thought out plan by declaring that it is the result of
‘spontaneity’ of capitalism! We will have occasion to see other interesting
consequences of this a little later.
Transcending Capitalism – The Need to Invent
Scenarios
So, if imperialism actually is what the Patnaiks have defined it to be, what can be
done about it? It is not surprising that the Patnaiks devote only a single page
of their book to this question. The 9th and the last chapter of
their book has a subsection which is titled ‘Transcending Capitalism’, which is
only a single page long. The importance that the Patnaiks ascribe to this
question and the difficulty that they evidently face in answering it is in
stark contrast with Lenin’s analysis of imperialism. Lenin has a whole chapter
in his book on imperialism dedicated to the question of ‘the place of
imperialism in history’, which starts with the following words:
“We have seen that in its economic essence
imperialism is monopoly capitalism. This in itself determines its place in
history, for monopoly that grows out of the soil of free competition, and
precisely out of free competition, is the transition from the capitalist system
to a higher socio-economic order.”
Imperialism is itself preparing all the objective
conditions needed for its transcendence and the establishment of a higher
socio-political order and Lenin discerns this movement in his study of
imperialism. Hence, Lenin does not have to ‘search’ for a solution to the
imperialist problem, the solution is suggested by imperialism itself, it just
has to be discerned. This solution presents itself to Lenin because he was true
to the dialectical method. The same happens with Marx too when he studied
capitalism using materialist dialectics.
“Communism is for us not a state of affairs
which is to be established, an ideal to which reality [will] have to adjust
itself. We call communism the real movement which abolishes the present state
of things. The conditions of this movement result from the premises now in
existence.”
The situation is very different with the Patnaiks.
Imperialism, defined and studied the way they have done, does not suggest a solution at all. The
objective conditions for the transcendence of imperialism is not forthcoming by
tracing its movement. It is a definite way in which capitalism has always dealt
with the problem of geographical asymmetry which exists outside of it. In this
sense, it won’t be an overstatement to say that imperialism does not show any
movement at all, its modus operandi changes, but that is it. Hence, the
Patnaiks have to break their heads to find a way of transcending capitalism and
even then, all they can come up with are half-baked propositions.
“The fact that capitalism necessarily imposes
income deflation and poverty upon the peasants and petty producers of the
periphery underscores both the need for transcending the capitalist system for
human progress and the difficulty of doing so. This difficulty arises from the
fact that a world-level worker-peasant alliance for overthrowing the system is
not practicable in the foreseeable future… the alternative scenario of
transcendence of capitalism that might be visualized is one where in particular
countries, especially of the periphery, worker- peasant alliances are forged
and advance politically by de-linking those countries from the web of
globalization, and hence from the hegemony of international finance capital.
But such delinking makes these attempts extremely weak and vulnerable to
imperialist counterattacks.” [63]
It can be seen that in the absence of a dialectical
theory of imperialism, Patnaiks are left with no other option but to conjure up
different ‘alternate scenarios’ or to suggest different strategies. At the end,
they concede defeat.
“Imperialism, in short, not only oppresses the
working people in the periphery but also makes any challenge to such oppression
by its victims that much more difficult.” [64]
But, true to their petty bourgeois credentials, they
never fail to offer us fantasies. The Patnaiks close their book with a flourish
which offers nothing but pious wishes.
“But imperialism is bringing the world to such an
impasse at present—an impasse characterized by economic crisis, stagnation, and
unemployment both in the metropolis and in the periphery; by unprecedented and
intolerable levels of oppression of peasants and petty producers in the
periphery … and by an acute threat to our ecosystem —that mass resistance to
it, as had happened in the context of the world wars that provided the backdrop
to the previous round of revolutions, can suddenly erupt anywhere. That could
usher in a whole new era of resistance and revolutions through which all
existing social conditions, including levels of consciousness, could alter with
astonishing rapidity.” [65]
Be positive, the authors say! Even though there is
nothing in our theory which suggest that imperialism, and with it capitalism,
can be transcended, even though our theory could not even trace such a movement
at all, still, revolutions can ‘suddenly erupt’ anywhere. One just have
to wait for it. Hope is what the Patnaiks have to offer, hope which is devoid
of any theoretical basis.
Welfare state and the ‘cooperative’
solution
For Lenin, imperialism develops in the course and
evolution of capitalism, when the growth of capitalism leads to monopolisation,
i.e., it is a stage of capitalism. But for the Patnaiks, imperialism is a way
in which capitalism tries to resolve a geographical contradiction. The
contradiction itself is not due to capitalism but is out there, was always
there, and will always be there, independent of any mode of production. The
Patnaiks say that imperialism arises because capitalism, in its ‘spontaneity’,
resolves this contradiction in a particular way. Imperialism for the Patnaiks
is “linked to capitalism as a social system”, but it is not a direct consequence
of capitalism, nor does it develop from inside capitalism. As it is a reaction
to something outside of it, this reaction attains, in Patnaiks’ work, a planned
nature, however much they try to dress it up as ‘spontaneous’. They declare
these reactions as spontaneous, but they increasingly take the concrete form of
plots and ploys in the book. The question that arises is whether such a
reaction of capitalism to a geographical asymmetry is unavoidable; Patnaiks
argue that this reaction is spontaneous, but is it inevitable? Their answer to
this question is not in the affirmative.
“Our theory of imperialism therefore is based on
the recognition of a basic trait of capitalism: namely, when it is faced with
two alternatives, one of which can be described as a “cooperative solution”
effected through state activism to the benefit of all, and the other at the
expense of the working population, it invariably chooses the latter.” [66]
They reiterate here concretely what they had already
said implicitly when analysing why land augmentation is impossible. There is
another alternative to imperialism, a ‘cooperative solution’, one which
capitalism refuses to take in its ‘spontaneity’. So it emerges that if you can
rein in the ‘spontaneous’ and ‘anarchic’ nature of capitalism, then this
problem may have another solution. And all reformists and social democrats have
a readymade mechanism for exactly doing this: the Welfare State.
We have already seen the Indian left’s approach
towards such a state; such a state is the only tangible solution they have to
offer to all the ills of capitalism. And these ‘illusions’ regarding the nature
and possibilities of welfare state has left its mark on this book also. The
authors characterise the neoliberal regime as follows in the book.
“…whereas during the dirigiste period, the
bourgeois state, even while promoting the development of capitalism, appeared
to be standing above classes and “looking after” the interests of all (and
hence making concessions to other classes as well, and controlling to an
extent the operations of the bourgeoisie), now the state becomes far more
tied to promoting the exclusive interests of the corporate- financial elite,
which is integrated with international finance capital” [67]
We know that the welfare state was not a mechanism
which tried to control capitalism against the wishes of the bourgeoisie,
it was an arrangement which put a tab on capital at the behest of the
bourgeoisie. A passing acquaintance with the Bombay plan is enough to make
this clear. So, the underlined part of
the above quote, which implies that the operations of the bourgeoisie can be
controlled by an ‘activist state’, is a pure illusion. It was done at a
particular conjuncture of world and Indian capitalism in which even the vanguard
of the bourgeois was favourable to it.
“The phenomena noted above, namely the withdrawal
of the state from its role of supporting, protecting, and promoting peasant
agriculture (and petty production in general), its apotheosizing “sound
finance” as demanded by international finance capital, and its reversion on
this pretext to a policy of imposing income deflation on the working people are
all indicative of a change in the class orientation of the state. Instead of
being an entity apparently standing above classes and mediating between them
(even as it promoted a relatively autonomous capitalist development, as the
dirigiste regime did), the state in the period of globalization becomes
associated almost exclusively with promoting the interests of international
finance capital and the domestic corporate-financial elite that becomes
integrated with it. The undermining of petty production that occurs is just the
other side of this coin.” [68]
The Patnaiks are indulging in a subtle form of
duplicity here; they stop short of claiming that the dirigisme state was above
classes, but state that it ‘appeared to be standing above classes’ and that it
was ‘apparently standing above classes and mediating between them’, even when
it was promoting capitalist development. But they also claim that the state was
‘making concessions to other classes as well, and controlling to an extent the
operations of the bourgeoisie’. So we are given a feeling that the welfare
state was doing this against the wishes of the bourgeois class. But that is
completely wrong, this was the route of Indian capitalist development selected
and ratified by the Indian bourgeoisie as per the Bombay plan. The Indian
big bourgeois correctly gauged that capitalism in India cannot be developed
without state support, state funding, protective regime and an assertive state
policy to enhance the living, educational and skill standards of the
population. Support for petty production was the bourgeoisie’s need because the
living standards and purchasing power of the population needed to increase.
After the bourgeois have developed enough strength to stand on its legs, they
shall take over and the state can withdraw. So it is not that the state was
above the bourgeois class before and now it’s ‘class orientation’ has changed
and it has become ‘associated almost exclusively with promoting the interests
of international finance capital and the domestic corporate-financial elite’,
it was always a bourgeois state which was bent upon realising the bourgeois strategy before and now. The
point is that the strategy
has changed!
The impression that emerges from the authors’
pronouncements is that dirigisme state was able to and can reign in the
anarchic and spontaneous excesses of capitalism. In particular, it can try and
resolve the geographical asymmetry in a ‘cooperative’ manner that does not lead
to imperialism. A single more step in this direction and you can claim that if
Sanders is the president of the US and Corbyn the PM of Brittan, then
imperialism can be reined in and the ‘cooperative’ solution embraced instead!
This is very much in keeping with the welfare state social democratic fantasies
of the Indian left.
Two Zones, Two Capitalisms!
We have already seen that the only solution to
imperialism that the Patnaiks have to offer is that of ‘de-linking’ from the
web of globalisation. Let us dwell on this solution a little. Let us say a
tropical country like India delink from the clutches of imperialism. What then?
By Patnaiks’ own admission, petty production is pervasive in these lands but it
is fast decaying. So delinking will give rise to development of capitalism as
they agree happened under dirigisme regime. What will be the character
of this capitalism which develops “undisturbed” in a tropical third world
country? Here, one argument by Patnaiks become very important.
“The tropical and subtropical regions were both
historically self-sufficient and are potentially capable of being self-
sufficient even today. The temperate regions neither were historically
self-sufficient nor are potentially self- sufficient even today. The living
standard of people living in the temperate region simply cannot be met through
the production within this region alone. They have to rely on imports of
tropical and subtropical products. The same, however, is not true of the
latter regions, which do not have to rely on imports of temperate products.”
[69]
The geographical asymmetry is advantageous to the
tropics and hence the capitalism which shall develop in the tropics after
delinking need not be imperialist! In fact, a much stronger conclusion
follows from the Patnaiks’ argument; tropical capitalism, under whatever
conditions, cannot be imperialist (as per the definition of imperialism by
Patnaiks). Temperate capitalism had to resort to imperialism to procure the products which could not be produced there,
but there is no need for such a strategy for tropical capitalism because they
were self-sufficient and are potentially capable of being self-sufficient even
today, according to the Patnaiks. That
is very convenient; no matter the development of monopoly in India, no matter
how much capital it exports to neighbouring countries and to Africa, no matter
the level of concentration, no matter the naked collusion between the Indian
state apparatus and its biggest business houses which is becoming clearer day
by day, Indian capitalism can NEVER BE IMPERIALIST according to the Patnaiks. A
really consoling thought to the Indian big bourgeoisie and the Indian reformist
left; imperialism is of temperate origin and the imperial virus does not stand
a chance against the self-sufficient tropical capitalism!
But that introduces a problem, as the Patnaiks had
already characterised capitalism in a particular way at the start of the book,
aiming to correct Marx.
“… in addition to the capital-wage labour
relationship, capitalism is characterized by an additional structural
relationship, and “imperialism” refers to that structural relationship.
That relationship necessarily has a spatial dimension and was as much a feature
of the colonial period as it is of contemporary capitalism: its essence lies in
the fact that capitalism, within which of course metropolitan capitalism has
the predominant position, must, in its “spontaneous” operation, act in ways
that tend to immiserate the traditional petty producers of the third world, who
constitute the overwhelming bulk of the working population of these countries.”
But we have already seen that the capitalism which
develops in tropics, following the Patnaiks’ own admission, need cannot be
imperialist at all. This leads to a particularly awkward situation:
temperate capitalism is characterised by two structural relationships, the
capital – wage labour one and imperialism. But the tropical capitalism can only
be characterised by the former alone as it has no need for imperialism owing to
its self-sufficiency brought about by a favourable geographical disposition. So we see that the geographical asymmetry
envisaged by Patnaiks is so all pervasive that there are even two capitalisms! A
temperate one which is structurally imperialistic and a tropical one which is
not!
So we see where ‘fantastic’ theorising has got the authors to, they are now
suggesting the existence of two types of capitalism. Of course, I have
no plan of testing the patience of the reader by discussing this ludicrous
suggestion anymore.
But I cannot but help wonder what will
happen to the peasants and petty producers of the tropical countries if the
Patnaiks solution of ‘de-linking’ is resorted to. Such de-linking will lead to
relatively autonomous national economies, we are told. Then, capitalism shall
grow and flourish in these national economies with no imperialist aspirations,
as tropical capitalism is not structurally characterised by imperialism, according
to the theory presented in this book. Thus, such a capitalism will be similar
to the one Marx studied, characterised only by capital – wage labour structural
relationship and shall follow the path that Marx studied. This means that in
its ‘spontaneity’ such a capitalism will immiserate the petty producers and
peasants and make capitalist production all pervasive. What shall be the
reaction of the Patnaiks to such a destruction of petty bourgeois in tropical
lands after de-linking? Now this destruction is not caused by imperialism, but
by the growth of an autonomous capitalism. So, the Patnaiks can no longer argue
that arresting this petty bourgeois slide is progressive. In such a case, will
they characterise the petty bourgeois destruction as objectively progressive,
as Marxists ought to do? If that is so, then their main argument in the book
seems to be suggesting something really amusing. The current impoverishment of
petty producers is to be halted because it is caused by imperialism. In order
to resist imperialism, we have to de-link and that will lead to the growth of
an autonomous version of capitalism. This version of capitalism has no need of
imperialism and will develop along the lines predicted by Marx. This means that
it will immiserate the petty producers. But this time such destruction of petty
production is progressive and should not be attempted to be reversed. So,
essentially, the argument is to prop up petty production now so that it can be
destroyed later in the proper scientific way. You save petty producers
now from the clutches of imperialism to deliver them to the national
bourgeoisie to be crushed, later. The Patnaiks may disagree saying that
they envisaged the de-linking process to be accompanied by strong welfare state
measures which will make sure that even the indigenous version of capitalism
cannot immiserate petty producers. Then, they are advancing an unabashed reformist
position which argues that destruction of petty production and wholesome
development of capitalism has to be curtailed to protect the petty bourgeois.
This works against the basic tenant of revolutionary Marxism which sees such
destruction as objectively progressive as they prepare the material conditions
for advancement to a higher stage of production.
However one looks at it, the Patnaiks’
theory runs into myriads of problems as soon as we start analysing it. If one
tries to take the Patnaiks’ arguments to their logical conclusion, then they
yield self-contradictory and amusing results, as we have seen many times. In
advancing a new theory of imperialism, the Patnaiks noted at the beginning of
their book itself that Marxism lacked a unified theory of imperialism which is
valid for both colonial and imperialist eras and that the conjuncture in
which Leninist theory of imperialism was valid has long past. First, Marxism
does not have a theory of imperialism valid for both colonial and imperial
phases because it recognises the qualitative difference between these two
phases. It asserts, with Lenin, that the political economy of the imperialist
phase is completely different from the colonialist one and that the category of imperialism is only valid for
the former phase. Second, the conjuncture in which Lenin’s theory of
imperialism is valid is not that of the First World War, as the Patnaiks
wrongly assumes, but that of monopoly capitalism. In this sense, Lenin’s theory
has lost none of its pertinence. But, in trying to devise a theory which will
account for all phases of capitalism and will also solve many of the reformist
left’s theoretical problems, the Patnaiks have come up with arguments which are
plain false in any conjuncture. Their book’s only importance is that it
shows the devious ways which petty bourgeois theorists are capable of taking to
evade the revolutionary conclusions of Marxism.
5. Raison d'être of Patnaiks’ Theory
We have already seen the sheer untenable
character of Patnaiks’ theory of imperialism. Harvey, in his commentary to the Patnaiks’
book, wondered: “…why, in the face of all this evident dynamism in the
global economy do the Patnaiks insist on the unreal concept of a fixed and
immutable “dead” agrarian space of a tropical landmass populated by
non-capitalist peasant producers destined for perpetual exploitation of metropolitan
capital as the latter’s primary lifeline to survival? Only the Patnaiks can
answer that question”. As we have detailed, the theory of imperialism
contrived by the Patnaiks is so full of glaring inconsistencies that the
question posed by Harvey is sure to occur to almost every intelligent reader. Based
on the critique presented, their theory’s raison d’etre becomes very
clear. Prabhat Patnaik and Utsa Patnaik are prominent representatives of the
reformist left political outfits in India, especially the CPI(M). But, in spite
of being reformists in ideology and social democrats in politics for many
decades now, neither these political
outfits nor their academic representatives like the Patnaiks have relinquished
the tag of ‘Marxists’ which they continue to use to fool their cadre and
sympathisers. It is evident that reformism, being a thoroughly petty bourgeois
trend, in impossible to be reconciled with Marxism which is thoroughly revolutionary
in its spirit, method and content. In section 1 of this article, we analysed
and listed out the political proposals advanced by the reformist left and their
intellectuals including the Patnaiks and pointed to the petty bourgeois
character of each of these proposals. These proposals and the politics based on
them cannot be justified based on Marxism. The real motivation behind the
theory of imperialism conjured up by the Patnaiks is that it effects a revision
of Marxism which drags it down to the petty bourgeois level. This revision
allows the Patnaiks to justify all the proposals of the reformist left by
picturing all of them as anti-imperialist!
The central point is the approach towards
petty production, especially in agriculture. The Marxian approach towards small
scale peasant farming is very well known and Marx and Lenin has written about
it extensively. But, the Indian left’s approach towards the agrarian question
has been completely different. The left has completely forsaken class struggle
in agrarian issues and now routinely fights for the ‘farmers’, the label under
which they club together large capitalist farmers, small and medium farmers
along with subsistence farmers and even agricultural labourers. The left no
longer base their agrarian analysis on the class differentiation of farmers and
peasants and their politics obfuscates the class struggle in the country side
between rural proletariat and the capitalist farmers. The left pictures the
whole farming community as a single entity which has common goals and demands for
which they bargain with the state. Needless to say that this approach has
nothing to do with the Marxian one, which is solidly based on class struggle. The
left’s class-less approach and its reformist politics complements each
other perfectly. The most regressive side of this politics is shown in the
question of petty peasant production. The disregard for class analysis allows
the left to categorise petty producers simply as ‘poor’ in need of support. Lenin
has castigated this type of class-less approach and has in the process
delineated the class root of the petty producer[70]:
“In the Populist
newspapers and magazines we often meet with the assertion that the workers and
the “working” peasantry belong to the same class. The absolute incorrectness of
this view is obvious to anyone who understands that more or less developed
capitalist production predominates in all modern states—i.e., capital rules the
market and transforms the masses of working people into wage-workers. The
so-called “working” peasant is in fact a small proprietor, or a petty
bourgeois, who nearly always either hires himself out to work for somebody else
or hires workers himself. Being a small proprietor, the “working” peasant also
vacillates in politics between the masters and the workers, between the
bourgeoisie and the proletariat.”
Lenin clearly understood the consequences of the
reformist obfuscation of the class nature of the peasant and hence, he
correctly underlined the Marxist approach to agrarian petty production[71]:
“The peasant question in modern capitalist states
most frequently gives rise to perplexity and vacillation among Marxists and to
most of the attacks on Marxism by bourgeois (professorial) political economy. Petty
production in agriculture is doomed to extinction and to an incredibly crushed
and oppressed position under capitalism, say the Marxists. Petty production
is dependent on big capital, is backward in comparison with large-scale
production in agriculture, and can only keep going by means of desperately
reduced consumption and laborious, arduous toil. The frittering away and waste
of human labour, the worst forms of dependence of the producer, exhaustion of
the peasant’s family, his cattle and his land—this is what capitalism
everywhere brings the peasant. There is no salvation for the peasant except
by joining in the activities of the proletariat, primarily those of the
wage-workers.”
This approach derives from Marx’s insight that the
petty bourgeois is progressive only when they join the ranks of the proletariat
in the fight against capital. But the reformist left envisages a completely
different type of salvation for petty production. They argue that petty
production has to be sustained on state support and by protection from national
and international competition from big capital. In supporting petty production,
they lower their politics to the petty bourgeois level and ends up raising
petty bourgeois slogans rather than proletarian ones. This doesn’t give the
left any problems on the ground, as the whole of their cadre base has been
converted to petty bourgeois orientation by decades of reformist politics. But
this pricks the soul of ‘academic’ representatives of the left who find it very
difficult to justify the political support of petty production. It is exactly
this problem that the Patnaiks’ theory addresses. By maintaining, as we already
saw, that the impoverishment of peasants in the periphery is not due to the
growth of capitalism but due to imperialism, the Patnaiks are attempting to
build theoretical justification for the left’s petty bourgeois politics. This
is the overriding purpose of their concocted theory of imperialism. The Patnaiks
are trying to build a theoretical edifice which will justify the reformist left’s
descent to petty bourgeois level. But, as we have seen, their effort comes a
cropper.
6. Conclusions
In the first section of this article, we
saw that the practical prescriptions espoused by the reformist Indian left
against the twin threats of a decaying capitalism and growing fascism are
thoroughly petty bourgeois in character. Instead of theorising the forward
march of the proletariat towards socialism, the Indian left envisages the
return to calm, crisis-less capitalism. Return to an activist
welfare state, autonomy from international finance capital, embracing a
‘democratic’, ‘egalitarian’ variety of nationalism, unqualified acceptance of
liberal democracy and uniting politically with other ‘progressive’ parties are
the left’s important strategies to achieve this. But in the age of global decay
of capitalism, it is becoming clearer every day that the capitalist mode of
production is unsustainable. It is also clear that the objective conditions
needed for transcending capitalism is ripening. Hence, from a Marxist view
point, the left’s above prescriptions and strategies are untenable and smacks
of crass reformism. The Patnaiks’ theory of imperialism is specifically
designed to solve
this theoretical difficulty; it makes the left’s strategies seem progressive. In defining
imperialism as ways in which the metropolitan core impoverishes petty producers
in the periphery including India, their theory renders a return to an activist
state and autonomy from international finance capitalism, anti-imperialist in character.
Return to an activist welfare state makes the embrace of liberal democracy
desirable and the plan for de-linking from globalisation means that an
egalitarian form of nationalism is progressive. Support of petty production
becomes anti-imperialist and so does uniting with petty bourgeois movements and
parties. With a single inspired definition of imperialism, the Patnaiks sweep away all of the Indian
lefts’ theoretical misgivings about lowering itself to the petty bourgeois
level. This definition and the theory based on it, converts all of the left’s
petty bourgeois positions into anti-imperialist ones. Their ingenuity is indeed
admirable. But there remains a minor catch; the definition advanced by the
Patnaiks is wrong, the theory that follows is ludicrous. The book, true to its
petty bourgeois orientation, is a sorry heap of inconsistencies,
self-contradictions and basic theoretical howlers. But when has such minor
considerations stopped real academicians from giving their fantasies
free rein!?
[1] ‘A Theory of
Imperialism’, Utsa Patnaik and Prabhat Patnaik, Columbia University Press, New
York, 2017. Emphasis mine.
[6] ‘A commentary on A
Theory of Imperialism’, David Harvey, included in ‘A Theory of
Imperialism’, Utsa Patnaik and Prabhat Patnaik, Columbia University Press, New
York, 2017.
[7] Harvey wonders, “…why, in the face of all this evident dynamism in the global
economy do the Patnaiks insist on the unreal concept of a fixed and immutable
“dead” agrarian space of a tropical landmass populated by non-capitalist
peasant producers destined for perpetual exploitation of metropolitan capital
as the latter’s primary lifeline to survival? Only the Patnaiks can answer that
question”, ibid, p. 172.
[8] It has to be kept in
kind that the Patnaiks are prominent academic representatives of Indian left.
[11] ‘The market that
failed – Neoliberal economic reforms in India’, C. P. Chandrasekhar and Jayati
Ghosh, Leftword Books, New Delhi, 2002.
[13] For my detailed take
on the correct interpretation of this interlude, see ‘Planning Commission -
Right's Intentions, Left's Reaction and the Way Forward’, available online
here: http://revolutionaryspring.blogspot.in/2015/01/planning-commission-rights-intentions.html
[14] ‘Things that the left
needs to do right’, Prabhat Patnaik, The Hindu, 24 May, 2016.
[15] So the left is to serve the whole of the people, not the
proletariat class! Lenin had something to say about such bourgeois use of the
word ‘people’: “Social democracy has fought, as is quite rightly fighting,
against the bourgeois-democratic abuse of the word ‘people’. It demands that
this word shall not be used to cover up the failure to understand class
antagonisms within the people.”
[16] ‘Hands off Lenin! -
The ‘Patnaik Conjecture’ and the travesty of Leninism’, Bipin Balaram,
available online at:
[17] ‘What it means to be ‘national’’, Prabhat Patnaik, The Hindu, 27
February, 2016.
[20] ‘The proletarian
revolution and the renegade Kautsky’, Lenin, Collected Works, Volume 28.
Emphasis mine.
[21] ‘A Theory of
Imperialism’, Utsa Patnaik and Prabhat Patnaik, Columbia University Press, New
York, 2017. Pp. 142, 144.
[33] ‘A Theory of
Imperialism’, Utsa Patnaik and Prabhat Patnaik, Columbia University Press, New York,
2017. Pp. 33-34.
[41] ‘A commentary on A
Theory of Imperialism’, David Harvey, included in ‘A Theory of Imperialism’,
Utsa Patnaik and Prabhat Patnaik, Columbia University Press, New York, 2017,
pp. 155-156.
[42] Ibid, p. 156.
[44] ‘A response to David
Harvey’s comments’, included in ‘A Theory of Imperialism’, Utsa Patnaik and
Prabhat Patnaik, Columbia University Press, New York, 2017, p. 180.
[45] ‘A commentary on A
Theory of Imperialism’, David Harvey, included in ‘A Theory of
Imperialism’, Utsa Patnaik and Prabhat Patnaik, Columbia University Press, New
York, 2017, p. 157.
[46] This has to be so as the authors claim to be presenting a unified
theory of imperialism which incorporates colonial and post-colonial phases.
[47] ‘A commentary on A
Theory of Imperialism’, David Harvey, included in ‘A Theory of
Imperialism’, Utsa Patnaik and Prabhat Patnaik, Columbia University Press, New
York, 2017, p. 162.
[48] ‘A response to David
Harvey’s comments’, included in ‘A Theory of Imperialism’, Utsa Patnaik and
Prabhat Patnaik, Columbia University Press, New York, 2017, p. 173.
[49] Ibid, p. 194.
[50] ‘A commentary on A
Theory of Imperialism’, David Harvey, included in ‘A Theory of
Imperialism’, Utsa Patnaik and Prabhat Patnaik, Columbia University Press, New
York, 2017, p. 159.
[53] ‘Introduction’ to
‘Capital Volume 1’ by Karl Marx, Penguin Classics Edition, 1990. Pp. 13.
Emphasis mine.
[54] ‘A Theory of
Imperialism’, Utsa Patnaik and Prabhat Patnaik, Columbia University Press, New
York, 2017. Pp. 31. Emphasis mine.
[55] ‘A Theory of
Imperialism’, Utsa Patnaik and Prabhat Patnaik, Columbia University Press, New
York, 2017. Pp. 31.
[66] ‘A response to David
Harvey’s comments’, included in ‘A Theory of Imperialism’, Utsa Patnaik and
Prabhat Patnaik, Columbia University Press, New York, 2017, p. 193.
[67] ‘A Theory of
Imperialism’, Utsa Patnaik and Prabhat Patnaik, Columbia University Press, New
York, 2017. Pp. 32. Emphasis mine.
No comments:
Post a Comment